
In the context of a majority cycle in which xis majority preferred to y, the electorate is incoherent with
respect to xand yin the sense that while there is an argument that xshould defeat y, in virtue of the
majority preference for xover y, there is also an opposing argument that xshould not defeat y, in virtue
of the path of majority preferences from yto x; e.g., yis majority preferred to z, who is majority preferred
to x. One natural measure of the degree of this incoherence is the strength of the opposing argument, which
is some monotonic function of the margins of the relevant majority preferences; e.g., the larger the margin
of yover zor of zover x, the more incoherent with the majority preference for xover y—and the smaller
those margins, the less incoherent with the majority preference for xover y. On this view, the following is
sufficient for P′to be no more incoherent than Pwith respect to xand y: the margin graph of P′is obtained
from that of Pby deleting or reducing the margins on zero or more edges not connecting xand yor by
deleting zero or more candidates other than xand y. Adopting this view about incoherence, Holliday and
Pacuit accept the core intuition behind IIA whenever contextual incoherence does not interfere, leading to
their axiom of Coherent IIA, which can be stated informally as follows:
•Coherent IIA (informally): if Pand P′are the same with respect to how each voter ranks xvs. y,
xdefeats yin P, and P′is not more incoherent than Pwith respect to xand y, then xmust also defeat
yin P′.
Holliday and Pacuit then prove that Split Cycle is the most resolute collective choice rule5satisfying the five
standard axioms plus Coherent IIA. Here “most resolute” means that for any other rule fthat satisfies the
six axioms, if xdefeats yaccording to f, then xdefeats yaccording to Split Cycle.
Holliday and Pacuit’s theorem may be viewed as characterizing Split Cycle as the unique collective choice
rule satisfying their six axioms plus a seventh axiom stating that the rule should be the most resolute rule
satisfying the first six axioms. In a sense, however, this characterization using the notion of resoluteness is
only half of a characterization of Split Cycle.6We would like axioms on a collective choice rule such that
for any rule fsatisfying the axioms, xdefeats yaccording to fif and only if xdefeats yaccording to Split
Cycle. Such an axiomatic characterization is the main result of the present paper.
Our new characterization of Split Cycle involves two natural axioms, which we prove are satisfied by
exactly the collective choice rules that refine Split Cycle:
•Coherent Defeat: if a majority of voters prefer xto y, and there is no majority cycle involving xand
y, then xdefeats y.
•Positive Involvement in Defeat: if ydoes not defeat xin profile P, and P′is obtained from Pby
adding one new voter who ranks xabove y, then ystill does not defeat xin P′.
Coherent Defeat is a point of common ground between Split Cycle, Ranked Pairs, Beat Path, and GOCHA
(Schwartz 1986): in the absence of cyclic incoherence, majority preference is sufficient for defeat. We will
discuss other ways of motivating Coherent Defeat below, drawing on Heitzig 2002.7The intuition behind
Positive Involvement in Defeat, a variable-electorate axiom, is similar to the intuition behind fixed-electorate
monotonicity axioms for collective choice rules, as stated in Blair and Pollak 1982: “additional support for a
5Technically, they characterize Split Cycle as what they call a variable-election collective choice rule, whose domain contains
profiles with different sets of candidates and voters (see Section 2.1 below). Until the end of this section, we use ‘collective
choice rule’ to refer to the variable-election variety.
6As Holliday and Pacuit (2021a, p. 501) write, “A natural next step would be to obtain another axiomatic characterization
of Split Cycle as the only VCCR satisfying some axioms without reference to resoluteness.”
7Heitzig’s (2004a) definition of an “immune” candidate is the same as that of a Split Cycle winner if we replace “stronger”
with “at least as strong” in his definition.
4