Stephen Hawking - A History of Science - 1 of 4

VIP免费
2024-12-03 0 0 732.09KB 156 页 5.9玖币
侵权投诉
A
HISTORY OF SCIENCE
BY
HENRY SMITH WILLIAMS, M.D., LL.D.
ASSISTED BY
EDWARD H. WILLIAMS, M.D.
IN FIVE VOLUMES
VOLUME I.
THE BEGINNINGS OF SCIENCE
BOOK I.
CONTENTS
CHAPTER I. PREHISTORIC SCIENCE
CHAPTER II. EGYPTIAN SCIENCE
CHAPTER III. SCIENCE OF BABYLONIA AND ASSYRIA
CHAPTER IV. THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE ALPHABET
CHAPTER V. THE BEGINNINGS OF GREEK SCIENCE
CHAPTER VI. THE EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHERS IN ITALY
CHAPTER VII. GREEK SCIENCE IN THE EARLY ATTIC PERIOD
CHAPTER VIII. POST-SOCRATIC SCIENCE AT ATHENS
CHAPTER IX. GREEK SCIENCE OF THE ALEXANDRIAN OR HELLENISTIC
PERIOD
CHAPTER X. SCIENCE OF THE ROMAN PERIOD
CHAPTER XI. A RETROSPECTIVE GLANCE AT CLASSICAL SCIENCE
APPENDIX
A HISTORY OF SCIENCE
BOOK I
Should the story that is about to be unfolded be found to lack
interest, the writers must stand convicted of unpardonable lack
of art. Nothing but dulness in the telling could mar the story,
for in itself it is the record of the growth of those ideas that
have made our race and its civilization what they are; of ideas
instinct with human interest, vital with meaning for our race;
fundamental in their influence on human development; part and
parcel of the mechanism of human thought on the one hand, and of
practical civilization on the other. Such a phrase as
"fundamental principles" may seem at first thought a hard saying,
but the idea it implies is less repellent than the phrase itself,
for the fundamental principles in question are so closely linked
with the present interests of every one of us that they lie
within the grasp of every average man and woman--nay, of every
well-developed boy and girl. These principles are not merely the
stepping-stones to culture, the prerequisites of knowledge--they
are, in themselves, an essential part of the knowledge of every
cultivated person.
It is our task, not merely to show what these principles are, but
to point out how they have been discovered by our predecessors.
We shall trace the growth of these ideas from their first vague
beginnings. We shall see how vagueness of thought gave way to
precision; how a general truth, once grasped and formulated, was
found to be a stepping-stone to other truths. We shall see that
there are no isolated facts, no isolated principles, in nature;
that each part of our story is linked by indissoluble bands with
that which goes before, and with that which comes after. For the
most part the discovery of this principle or that in a given
sequence is no accident. Galileo and Keppler must precede Newton.
Cuvier and Lyall must come before Darwin;--Which, after all, is
no more than saying that in our Temple of Science, as in any
other piece of architecture, the foundation must precede the
superstructure.
We shall best understand our story of the growth of science if we
think of each new principle as a stepping-stone which must fit
into its own particular niche; and if we reflect that the entire
structure of modern civilization would be different from what it
is, and less perfect than it is, had not that particular
stepping-stone been found and shaped and placed in position.
Taken as a whole, our stepping-stones lead us up and up towards
the alluring heights of an acropolis of knowledge, on which
stands the Temple of Modern Science. The story of the building of
this wonderful structure is in itself fascinating and beautiful.
I. PREHISTORIC SCIENCE
To speak of a prehistoric science may seem like a contradiction
of terms. The word prehistoric seems to imply barbarism, while
science, clearly enough, seems the outgrowth of civilization; but
rightly considered, there is no contradiction. For, on the one
hand, man had ceased to be a barbarian long before the beginning
of what we call the historical period; and, on the other hand,
science, of a kind, is no less a precursor and a cause of
civilization than it is a consequent. To get this clearly in
mind, we must ask ourselves: What, then, is science? The word
runs glibly enough upon the tongue of our every-day speech, but
it is not often, perhaps, that they who use it habitually ask
themselves just what it means. Yet the answer is not difficult. A
little attention will show that science, as the word is commonly
used, implies these things: first, the gathering of knowledge
through observation; second, the classification of such
knowledge, and through this classification, the elaboration of
general ideas or principles. In the familiar definition of
Herbert Spencer, science is organized knowledge.
Now it is patent enough, at first glance, that the veriest savage
must have been an observer of the phenomena of nature. But it may
not be so obvious that he must also have been a classifier of his
observations--an organizer of knowledge. Yet the more we consider
the case, the more clear it will become that the two methods are
too closely linked together to be dissevered. To observe outside
phenomena is not more inherent in the nature of the mind than to
draw inferences from these phenomena. A deer passing through the
forest scents the ground and detects a certain odor. A sequence
of ideas is generated in the mind of the deer. Nothing in the
deer's experience can produce that odor but a wolf; therefore the
scientific inference is drawn that wolves have passed that way.
But it is a part of the deer's scientific knowledge, based on
previous experience, individual and racial; that wolves are
dangerous beasts, and so, combining direct observation in the
present with the application of a general principle based on past
experience, the deer reaches the very logical conclusion that it
may wisely turn about and run in another direction. All this
implies, essentially, a comprehension and use of scientific
principles; and, strange as it seems to speak of a deer as
possessing scientific knowledge, yet there is really no absurdity
in the statement. The deer does possess scientific knowledge;
knowledge differing in degree only, not in kind, from the
knowledge of a Newton. Nor is the animal, within the range of its
intelligence, less logical, less scientific in the application of
that knowledge, than is the man. The animal that could not make
accurate scientific observations of its surroundings, and deduce
accurate scientific conclusions from them, would soon pay the
penalty of its lack of logic.
What is true of man's precursors in the animal scale is, of
course, true in a wider and fuller sense of man himself at the
very lowest stage of his development. Ages before the time which
the limitations of our knowledge force us to speak of as the dawn
of history, man had reached a high stage of development. As a
social being, he had developed all the elements of a primitive
civilization. If, for convenience of classification, we speak of
his state as savage, or barbaric, we use terms which, after all,
are relative, and which do not shut off our primitive ancestors
from a tolerably close association with our own ideals. We know
that, even in the Stone Age, man had learned how to domesticate
animals and make them useful to him, and that he had also learned
to cultivate the soil. Later on, doubtless by slow and painful
stages, he attained those wonderful elements of knowledge that
enabled him to smelt metals and to produce implements of bronze,
and then of iron. Even in the Stone Age he was a mechanic of
marvellous skill, as any one of to-day may satisfy himself by
attempting to duplicate such an implement as a chipped
arrow-head. And a barbarian who could fashion an axe or a knife
of bronze had certainly gone far in his knowledge of scientific
principles and their practical application. The practical
application was, doubtless, the only thought that our primitive
ancestor had in mind; quite probably the question as to
principles that might be involved troubled him not at all. Yet,
in spite of himself, he knew certain rudimentary principles of
science, even though he did not formulate them.
Let us inquire what some of these principles are. Such an inquiry
will, as it were, clear the ground for our structure of science.
It will show the plane of knowledge on which historical
investigation begins. Incidentally, perhaps, it will reveal to us
unsuspected affinities between ourselves and our remote ancestor.
Without attempting anything like a full analysis, we may note in
passing, not merely what primitive man knew, but what he did not
know; that at least a vague notion may be gained of the field for
scientific research that lay open for historic man to cultivate.
It must be understood that the knowledge of primitive man, as we
are about to outline it, is inferential. We cannot trace the
development of these principles, much less can we say who
discovered them. Some of them, as already suggested, are man's
heritage from non-human ancestors. Others can only have been
grasped by him after he had reached a relatively high stage of
human development. But all the principles here listed must surely
have been parts of our primitive ancestor's knowledge before
those earliest days of Egyptian and Babylonian civilization, the
records of which constitute our first introduction to the
so-called historical period. Taken somewhat in the order of their
probable discovery, the scientific ideas of primitive man may be
roughly listed as follows:
1. Primitive man must have conceived that the earth is flat and
of limitless extent. By this it is not meant to imply that he had
a distinct conception of infinity, but, for that matter, it
cannot be said that any one to-day has a conception of infinity
that could be called definite. But, reasoning from experience and
the reports of travellers, there was nothing to suggest to early
man the limit of the earth. He did, indeed, find in his
wanderings, that changed climatic conditions barred him from
farther progress; but beyond the farthest reaches of his
migrations, the seemingly flat land-surfaces and water-surfaces
stretched away unbroken and, to all appearances, without end. It
would require a reach of the philosophical imagination to
conceive a limit to the earth, and while such imaginings may have
been current in the prehistoric period, we can have no proof of
them, and we may well postpone consideration of man's early
dreamings as to the shape of the earth until we enter the
historical epoch where we stand on firm ground.
2. Primitive man must, from a very early period, have observed
that the sun gives heat and light, and that the moon and stars
seem to give light only and no heat. It required but a slight
extension of this observation to note that the changing phases of
the seasons were associated with the seeming approach and
recession of the sun. This observation, however, could not have
been made until man had migrated from the tropical regions, and
had reached a stage of mechanical development enabling him to
live in subtropical or temperate zones. Even then it is
conceivable that a long period must have elapsed before a direct
causal relation was felt to exist between the shifting of the sun
and the shifting of the seasons; because, as every one knows, the
periods of greatest heat in summer and greatest cold in winter
usually come some weeks after the time of the solstices. Yet, the
fact that these extremes of temperature are associated in some
way with the change of the sun's place in the heavens must, in
time, have impressed itself upon even a rudimentary intelligence.
It is hardly necessary to add that this is not meant to imply any
definite knowledge of the real meaning of, the seeming
oscillations of the sun. We shall see that, even at a relatively
late period, the vaguest notions were still in vogue as to the
cause of the sun's changes of position.
That the sun, moon, and stars move across the heavens must
obviously have been among the earliest scientific observations.
It must not be inferred, however, that this observation implied a
necessary conception of the complete revolution of these bodies
about the earth. It is unnecessary to speculate here as to how
the primitive intelligence conceived the transfer of the sun from
the western to the eastern horizon, to be effected each night,
for we shall have occasion to examine some historical
speculations regarding this phenomenon. We may assume, however,
that the idea of the transfer of the heavenly bodies beneath the
earth (whatever the conception as to the form of that body) must
early have presented itself.
It required a relatively high development of the observing
faculties, yet a development which man must have attained ages
before the historical period, to note that the moon has a
secondary motion, which leads it to shift its relative position
in the heavens, as regards the stars; that the stars themselves,
on the other hand, keep a fixed relation as regards one another,
with the notable exception of two or three of the most brilliant
members of the galaxy, the latter being the bodies which came to
be known finally as planets, or wandering stars. The wandering
propensities of such brilliant bodies as Jupiter and Venus cannot
well have escaped detection. We may safely assume, however, that
these anomalous motions of the moon and planets found no
explanation that could be called scientific until a relatively
late period.
3. Turning from the heavens to the earth, and ignoring such
primitive observations as that of the distinction between land
and water, we may note that there was one great scientific law
which must have forced itself upon the attention of primitive
man. This is the law of universal terrestrial gravitation. The
word gravitation suggests the name of Newton, and it may excite
surprise to hear a knowledge of gravitation ascribed to men who
preceded that philosopher by, say, twenty-five or fifty thousand
years. Yet the slightest consideration of the facts will make it
clear that the great central law that all heavy bodies fall
directly towards the earth, cannot have escaped the attention of
the most primitive intelligence. The arboreal habits of our
primitive ancestors gave opportunities for constant observation
of the practicalities of this law. And, so soon as man had
developed the mental capacity to formulate ideas, one of the
earliest ideas must have been the conception, however vaguely
phrased in words, that all unsupported bodies fall towards the
earth. The same phenomenon being observed to operate on
water-surfaces, and no alteration being observed in its operation
in different portions of man's habitat, the most primitive
wanderer must have come to have full faith in the universal
action of the observed law of gravitation. Indeed, it is
inconceivable that he can have imagined a place on the earth
where this law does not operate. On the other hand, of course, he
never grasped the conception of the operation of this law beyond
the close proximity of the earth. To extend the reach of
gravitation out to the moon and to the stars, including within
its compass every particle of matter in the universe, was the
work of Newton, as we shall see in due course. Meantime we shall
better understand that work if we recall that the mere local fact
of terrestrial gravitation has been the familiar knowledge of all
generations of men. It may further help to connect us in sympathy
with our primeval ancestor if we recall that in the attempt to
explain this fact of terrestrial gravitation Newton made no
advance, and we of to-day are scarcely more enlightened than the
man of the Stone Age. Like the man of the Stone Age, we know that
an arrow shot into the sky falls back to the earth. We can
calculate, as he could not do, the arc it will describe and the
exact speed of its fall; but as to why it returns to earth at
all, the greatest philosopher of to-day is almost as much in the
dark as was the first primitive bowman that ever made the
experiment.
Other physical facts going to make up an elementary science of
mechanics, that were demonstratively known to prehistoric man,
were such as these: the rigidity of solids and the mobility of
liquids; the fact that changes of temperature transform solids to
liquids and vice versa--that heat, for example, melts copper and
even iron, and that cold congeals water; and the fact that
friction, as illustrated in the rubbing together of two sticks,
may produce heat enough to cause a fire. The rationale of this
last experiment did not receive an explanation until about the
beginning of the nineteenth century of our own era. But the
experimental fact was so well known to prehistoric man that he
employed this method, as various savage tribes employ it to this
day, for the altogether practical purpose of making a fire; just
as he employed his practical knowledge of the mutability of
solids and liquids in smelting ores, in alloying copper with tin
to make bronze, and in casting this alloy in molds to make
various implements and weapons. Here, then, were the germs of an
elementary science of physics. Meanwhile such observations as
that of the solution of salt in water may be considered as giving
a first lesson in chemistry, but beyond such altogether
rudimentary conceptions chemical knowledge could not have
gone--unless, indeed, the practical observation of the effects of
fire be included; nor can this well be overlooked, since scarcely
another single line of practical observation had a more direct
influence in promoting the progress of man towards the heights of
civilization.
4. In the field of what we now speak of as biological knowledge,
primitive man had obviously the widest opportunity for practical
observation. We can hardly doubt that man attained, at an early
day, to that conception of identity and of difference which Plato
places at the head of his metaphysical system. We shall urge
presently that it is precisely such general ideas as these that
were man's earliest inductions from observation, and hence that
came to seem the most universal and "innate" ideas of his
mentality. It is quite inconceivable, for example, that even the
most rudimentary intelligence that could be called human could
fail to discriminate between living things and, let us say, the
rocks of the earth. The most primitive intelligence, then, must
have made a tacit classification of the natural objects about it
into the grand divisions of animate and inanimate nature.
Doubtless the nascent scientist may have imagined life animating
many bodies that we should call inanimate--such as the sun,
wandering planets, the winds, and lightning; and, on the other
hand, he may quite likely have relegated such objects as trees to
the ranks of the non-living; but that he recognized a fundamental
distinction between, let us say, a wolf and a granite bowlder we
cannot well doubt. A step beyond this--a step, however, that may
have required centuries or millenniums in the taking--must have
carried man to a plane of intelligence from which a primitive
Aristotle or Linnaeus was enabled to note differences and
resemblances connoting such groups of things as fishes, birds,
and furry beasts. This conception, to be sure, is an abstraction
of a relatively high order. We know that there are savage races
to-day whose language contains no word for such an abstraction as
bird or tree. We are bound to believe, then, that there were long
ages of human progress during which the highest man had attained
no such stage of abstraction; but, on the other hand, it is
equally little in question that this degree of mental development
had been attained long before the opening of our historical
period. The primeval man, then, whose scientific knowledge we are
attempting to predicate, had become, through his conception of
fishes, birds, and hairy animals as separate classes, a
scientific zoologist of relatively high attainments.
In the practical field of medical knowledge, a certain stage of
development must have been reached at a very early day. Even
animals pick and choose among the vegetables about them, and at
times seek out certain herbs quite different from their ordinary
food, practising a sort of instinctive therapeutics. The cat's
fondness for catnip is a case in point. The most primitive man,
then, must have inherited a racial or instinctive knowledge of
the medicinal effects of certain herbs; in particular he must
have had such elementary knowledge of toxicology as would enable
him to avoid eating certain poisonous berries. Perhaps, indeed,
we are placing the effect before the cause to some extent; for,
after all, the animal system possesses marvellous powers of
adaption, and there is perhaps hardly any poisonous vegetable
which man might not have learned to eat without deleterious
effect, provided the experiment were made gradually. To a certain
extent, then, the observed poisonous effects of numerous plants
upon the human system are to be explained by the fact that our
ancestors have avoided this particular vegetable. Certain fruits
and berries might have come to have been a part of man's diet,
had they grown in the regions he inhabited at an early day, which
now are poisonous to his system. This thought, however, carries
us too far afield. For practical purposes, it suffices that
certain roots, leaves, and fruits possess principles that are
poisonous to the human system, and that unless man had learned in
some way to avoid these, our race must have come to disaster. In
point of fact, he did learn to avoid them; and such evidence
implied, as has been said, an elementary knowledge of toxicology.
Coupled with this knowledge of things dangerous to the human
system, there must have grown up, at a very early day, a belief
in the remedial character of various vegetables as agents to
combat disease. Here, of course, was a rudimentary therapeutics,
a crude principle of an empirical art of medicine. As just
suggested, the lower order of animals have an instinctive
knowledge that enables them to seek out remedial herbs (though we
probably exaggerate the extent of this instinctive knowledge);
and if this be true, man must have inherited from his prehuman
ancestors this instinct along with the others. That he extended
this knowledge through observation and practice, and came early
to make extensive use of drugs in the treatment of disease, is
placed beyond cavil through the observation of the various
existing barbaric tribes, nearly all of whom practice elaborate
systems of therapeutics. We shall have occasion to see that even
within historic times the particular therapeutic measures
employed were often crude, and, as we are accustomed to say,
unscientific; but even the crudest of them are really based upon
scientific principles, inasmuch as their application implies the
deduction of principles of action from previous observations.
Certain drugs are applied to appease certain symptoms of disease
because in the belief of the medicine-man such drugs have proved
beneficial in previous similar cases.
All this, however, implies an appreciation of the fact that man
is subject to "natural" diseases, and that if these diseases are
not combated, death may result. But it should be understood that
the earliest man probably had no such conception as this.
Throughout all the ages of early development, what we call
"natural" disease and "natural" death meant the onslaught of a
tangible enemy. A study of this question leads us to some very
curious inferences. The more we look into the matter the more the
thought forces itself home to us that the idea of natural death,
as we now conceive it, came to primitive man as a relatively late
scientific induction. This thought seems almost startling, so
axiomatic has the conception "man is mortal" come to appear. Yet
a study of the ideas of existing savages, combined with our
knowledge of the point of view from which historical peoples
regard disease, make it more probable that the primitive
conception of human life did not include the idea of necessary
death. We are told that the Australian savage who falls from a
tree and breaks his neck is not regarded as having met a natural
death, but as having been the victim of the magical practices of
the "medicine-man" of some neighboring tribe. Similarly, we shall
find that the Egyptian and the Babylonian of the early historical
period conceived illness as being almost invariably the result of
the machinations of an enemy. One need but recall the
superstitious observances of the Middle Ages, and the yet more
recent belief in witchcraft, to realize how generally disease has
been personified as a malicious agent invoked by an unfriendly
mind. Indeed, the phraseology of our present-day speech is still
reminiscent of this; as when, for example, we speak of an "attack
of fever," and the like.
When, following out this idea, we picture to ourselves the
conditions under which primitive man lived, it will be evident at
once how relatively infrequent must have been his observation of
what we usually term natural death. His world was a world of
strife; he lived by the chase; he saw animals kill one another;
he witnessed the death of his own fellows at the hands of
enemies. Naturally enough, then, when a member of his family was
"struck down" by invisible agents, he ascribed this death also to
violence, even though the offensive agent was concealed.
Moreover, having very little idea of the lapse of time--being
quite unaccustomed, that is, to reckon events from any fixed
era--primitive man cannot have gained at once a clear conception
of age as applied to his fellows. Until a relatively late stage
of development made tribal life possible, it cannot have been
usual for man to have knowledge of his grandparents; as a rule he
did not know his own parents after he had passed the adolescent
stage and had been turned out upon the world to care for himself.
If, then, certain of his fellow-beings showed those evidences of
infirmity which we ascribe to age, it did not necessarily follow
that he saw any association between such infirmities and the
length of time which those persons had lived. The very fact that
some barbaric nations retain the custom of killing the aged and
infirm, in itself suggests the possibility that this custom arose
before a clear conception had been attained that such drags upon
the community would be removed presently in the natural order of
things. To a person who had no clear conception of the lapse of
time and no preconception as to the limited period of man's life,
the infirmities of age might very naturally be ascribed to the
repeated attacks of those inimical powers which were understood
sooner or later to carry off most members of the race. And
coupled with this thought would go the conception that inasmuch
as some people through luck had escaped the vengeance of all
their enemies for long periods, these same individuals might
continue to escape for indefinite periods of the future. There
were no written records to tell primeval man of events of long
ago. He lived in the present, and his sweep of ideas scarcely
carried him back beyond the limits of his individual memory. But
memory is observed to be fallacious. It must early have been
noted that some people recalled events which other participants
in them had quite forgotten, and it may readily enough have been
inferred that those members of the tribe who spoke of events
which others could not recall were merely the ones who were
gifted with the best memories. If these reached a period when
their memories became vague, it did not follow that their
recollections had carried them back to the beginnings of their
lives. Indeed, it is contrary to all experience to believe that
any man remembers all the things he has once known, and the
observed fallaciousness and evanescence of memory would thus tend
to substantiate rather than to controvert the idea that various
members of a tribe had been alive for an indefinite period.
Without further elaborating the argument, it seems a justifiable
inference that the first conception primitive man would have of
his own life would not include the thought of natural death, but
would, conversely, connote the vague conception of endless life.
Our own ancestors, a few generations removed, had not got rid of
this conception, as the perpetual quest of the spring of eternal
youth amply testifies. A naturalist of our own day has suggested
that perhaps birds never die except by violence. The thought,
then, that man has a term of years beyond which "in the nature of
things," as the saying goes, he may not live, would have dawned
but gradually upon the developing intelligence of successive
generations of men; and we cannot feel sure that he would fully
have grasped the conception of a "natural" termination of human
life until he had shaken himself free from the idea that disease
is always the result of the magic practice of an enemy. Our
observation of historical man in antiquity makes it somewhat
doubtful whether this conception had been attained before the
close of the prehistoric period. If it had, this conception of
the mortality of man was one of the most striking scientific
inductions to which prehistoric man attained. Incidentally, it
may be noted that the conception of eternal life for the human
body being a more primitive idea than the conception of natural
death, the idea of the immortality of the spirit would be the
most natural of conceptions. The immortal spirit, indeed, would
be but a correlative of the immortal body, and the idea which we
shall see prevalent among the Egyptians that the soul persists
only as long as the body is intact--the idea upon which the
practice of mummifying the dead depended--finds a ready
explanation. But this phase of the subject carries us somewhat
afield. For our present purpose it suffices to have pointed out
that the conception of man's mortality--a conception which now
seems of all others the most natural and "innate"--was in all
probability a relatively late scientific induction of our
primitive ancestors.
5. Turning from the consideration of the body to its mental
complement, we are forced to admit that here, also, our primitive
man must have made certain elementary observations that underlie
such sciences as psychology, mathematics, and political economy.
The elementary emotions associated with hunger and with satiety,
with love and with hatred, must have forced themselves upon the
earliest intelligence that reached the plane of conscious
self-observation. The capacity to count, at least to the number
four or five, is within the range of even animal intelligence.
Certain savages have gone scarcely farther than this; but our
primeval ancestor, who was forging on towards civilization, had
learned to count his fingers and toes, and to number objects
about him by fives and tens in consequence, before be passed
beyond the plane of numerous existing barbarians. How much beyond
this he had gone we need not attempt to inquire; but the
relatively high development of mathematics in the early
historical period suggests that primeval man had attained a not
inconsiderable knowledge of numbers. The humdrum vocation of
looking after a numerous progeny must have taught the mother the
rudiments of addition and subtraction; and the elements of
multiplication and division are implied in the capacity to carry
on even the rudest form of barter, such as the various tribes
must have practised from an early day.
摘要:

AHISTORYOFSCIENCEBYHENRYSMITHWILLIAMS,M.D.,LL.D.ASSISTEDBYEDWARDH.WILLIAMS,M.D.INFIVEVOLUMESVOLUMEI.THEBEGINNINGSOFSCIENCEBOOKI.CONTENTSCHAPTERI.PREHISTORICSCIENCECHAPTERII.EGYPTIANSCIENCECHAPTERIII.SCIENCEOFBABYLONIAANDASSYRIACHAPTERIV.THEDEVELOPMENTOFTHEALPHABETCHAPTERV.THEBEGINNINGSOFGREEKSCIENCE...

展开>> 收起<<
Stephen Hawking - A History of Science - 1 of 4.pdf

共156页,预览10页

还剩页未读, 继续阅读

声明:本站为文档C2C交易模式,即用户上传的文档直接被用户下载,本站只是中间服务平台,本站所有文档下载所得的收益归上传人(含作者)所有。玖贝云文库仅提供信息存储空间,仅对用户上传内容的表现方式做保护处理,对上载内容本身不做任何修改或编辑。若文档所含内容侵犯了您的版权或隐私,请立即通知玖贝云文库,我们立即给予删除!
分类:外语学习 价格:5.9玖币 属性:156 页 大小:732.09KB 格式:PDF 时间:2024-12-03

开通VIP享超值会员特权

  • 多端同步记录
  • 高速下载文档
  • 免费文档工具
  • 分享文档赚钱
  • 每日登录抽奖
  • 优质衍生服务
/ 156
客服
关注