冯友兰-中国哲学简史-英文原版

VIP免费
2024-12-02 0 0 1.23MB 232 页 5.9玖币
侵权投诉
AUTHOR'S PREFACE
A SHORT history of any subject should not simply be an abridgement of a larger one. It should
b
e a picture complete in itself, rather than a mere inventory of names and "isms.' To achieve this,
the author should, as a Chinese expression says, "have the whole history in his mind. Only then
can he give the reader an adequate and well-rounded account within his chosen limited scope.
According to Chinese historiography, a good historian must have wide scholarship in order to
master all his materials, sound judgment to make proper selection of them, and literary talent in
order to tell his story in an interesting way. In writing a short history, intended for a general
public, the author certainly has less chance to display his scholarship, but he needs more
selective judgment and literary talent than he would for writing a longer and strictly scholarly
work.
In preparing this work, I have tried to use my best judgment in selecting what I conside
r
important and relevant from materials which I have mastered. I was very fortunate, however, to
have as editor Dr. Derk Bodde, who has used his literary talent to make the style of the boo
k
interesting, readable, and comprehensible to the Western reader. He has also made suggestions
regarding the selection and arrangement of the material.
Being a short history, this book serves as no more than an introduction to the study of Chinese
p
hilosophy. If the reader wishes to know more about the subject, I would refer him to my large
r
work, A History of Chinese Philosophy. The first volume of this has been translated by Dr.
Bodde, and he is now translating the second one; also to my more recent work, The Spirit o
f
Chinese Philosophy, translated by Mr. E. R. Hughes of Oxford University. Both works are
mentioned in the bibliography compiled by Dr. Bodde at the end of the present book.
Acknowledgements are due to both Dr. Bodde and Mr.Hughes, from whose books I have
borrowed some translations of the Chinese texts appearing herein.
In publishing this book, I welcome the opportunity of expressing my thanks to the Rockefeller
Foundation for the grant which made it possible for me to come from China to the University o
f
Pennsylvania as Visiting Professor during the year 1946-47, and which resulted in the writing of this
book. Also, I wish to thank my colleagues and students in the Department of Oriental Studies for their
cooperation and encouragement, and especially Dr. Bodde, Associate Professor of Chinese. I am likewise
grateful to Dr. A. W. Hummel,Chief of the Asiatic Division, Library of Congress, for his encouragement
and help in making arrangements for the publication of the book.
FUNC.YU-LAN
J
une, 194
7
University of Pennsylvania
O04
CHAPTER 1
PIRIT OF CHINESE PHILOSOPHY
1 HE place which philosophy has occupied in Chinese civilization has been comparable to that o
f
religion in other civilizations. In China, philosophy has been every educated person s concern. In the
old days, if a man were educated at all, the first education he received was in philosophy. When chil-
dren went to school, the Four Books, which consist of the Confucian Analects, the Book of Mencius, the
Great Learning, and the Doctrine of the Mean, were the first ones they were taught to read. The Fou
r
B
ooks were the most important texts of Neo -Confucianist philosophy. Sometimes when the children
were just begining to learn the characters, they were given a sort of textbook to read. This was known
as the Three Characters Classic, and was so called because each sentence in the book consisted of three
characters arranged so that when recited they produced a rhythmic effect, and thus helped the children
to memorize them more easily. This book was in reality a primer, and the very first statement in it is
that "the nature of man is originally good." This is one of the fundamental ideas of Mencius'
philosophy.
P
lace of Philosophy in Chinese Civilization
To the Westerner, who sees that the life of the Chinese people is permeated with Confucianism, i
appears that Confucianism is a religion. As a matter of fact, however, Confucianism is no more
a
religion than, say, Pla-tonism or Aristotelianism. It is true that the Four Books have been the Bible o
f
the Chinese people, but in the Four Books there is no story of creation, and no mention of a heaven o
r
hell.
Of course, the terms philosophy and religion are both ambiguous, Philoso
p
hy and religion may have
entirely different meanings for different people. When men talk about philosophy or religion, they may
have quite different ideas in their minds concerning them. For my part, what I call philosophy is
systematic, reflective thinking on life. Every man, who has not yet died, is in life. But there are no
t
many who think reflectively on life, and still fewer
OO2 THE SPIRIT OF CHINESE PHILOSOPHY
whose reflective thinking is systematic. A philosopher must philosophize; that is to say, he must thin
k
reflectively on life, and then express his thoughts systematically.
This kind of thinking is called reflective because it takes life as its object. The theory of life, the
theory of the universe, and the theory of knowledge all emerge from this type of thinking. The theory o
f
the universe arises because the universe is the background of life—the stage on which the drama of life
takes place. The theory of knowledge emerges because thinking is itself knowledge. According to some
philosophers of the West, in order to think, we must first find out what we can think; that is to say,
before we start to think about life, we must first think our thinking.
Such theories are all the products of reflective thinking. The very concept of life, the very concept o
f
the universe, and the very concept of knowledge are also the products of reflective thinking. No matte
r
whether we think about life or whether we talk about it, we are all in the midst of it. And no matte
r
whether we think or speak about the universe, we are all a part of it. Now, what the philosophers call
the universe is not the same as what the physicists have in mind when they refer to it. What the
philosophers call the universe is the totality of all that is. It is equivalent to what the ancient Chinese
p
hilosopher, Hui Shih, called "The Great One," which is defined as that which has nothing beyond. So
everyone and everything must be considered part of the universe. When one thinks about the universe,
one is thinking reflectively.
When we think about knowledge or speak about knowledge, this thinking and speaking are
themselves knowledge. To use an expression of Aristotle, it is "thinking on thinking"; and this is
reflective thinking. Here is the vicious circle which those philosophers follow who insist that before we
think we must first think about our thinking; just as if we had another faculty with which we could thin
k
about thinking! As a matter of fact, the faculty with which we think about thinking is the very same
faculty with which we think. If we are skeptical about the capacity of our thinking in regard to life an
d
the universe, we have the same reason to be skeptical about the capacity of our thinking in regard to
thinking.
Religion also has something to do with life. In the heart of every great religion there is a philosophy.
In fact, every great religion is a philosophy with a certain amount of superstructure, which consists o
f
superstitions, dogmas, rituals, and institutions. This is what 1 call religion.
If one understands the term religion in this sense, which does not really differ very much from
common usage, one sees that Confucianism cannot be considered a religion. People have bee
n
accustomed to say that there were three religions in China: Confucianism, Taoism, and Buddhism. Bu
t
Confucianism, as we have seen, is not a religion. As to Taoism, there is a distinction between Taoism as
a philosophy, which is called Too chia (the Taoist school), and the Taoist religion {Too chiao). Thei
r
teachings are not only dif-
OP4 THE SPIRIT OF CHINESE PHILOSOPHY
God is really the universe. Strictly speaking, the love of God in Christianity is not really super-moral.
This is because God, in Christianity, is a personality, and consequently the love of God by man is
comparable to the love of a father by his son, which is a moral value. Therefore, the love of God i
n
Christianity is open to question as a super-moral value. It is a quasi super-moral value, while the love o
f
God in the philosophy of Spinoza is a real super-moral value.
To answer the above queslions, I would say that the craving for something beyond the present actual
world is one of the innate desires of mankind, and the Chinese people are no exception to this rule. They
have not had much concern with religion because they have had so much concern with philoso
p
hy. They
are not religious because they are philosophical. In philosophy they satisfy their craving for what is
beyond the present actual world. In philosophy also they have the super-moral values expressed an
d
appreciated, and in living according to philosophy these super-moral values are experienced.
According to the tradition of Chinese philosophy, its function is not the increase of positive
knowledge (by positive knowledge I mean information regarding matters of fact), but the elevation of the
mind—a reaching out for what is beyond the present actual world, and for the values that are higher tha
n
the moral ones. It was said by the Lao-tzu: To work on learning is to increase day by day; to work on
Tao (the Way, the Truth) is to decrease day by day." (See ch. 48.) I am not concerned with the difference
between increasing and decreasing, nor do I quite agree with this saying of Lao-tzu. I quote it only to
show that in the tradition of Chinese philosophy there is a distinction between working on learning an
d
working on Tao (the Way). The purpose of the former is what I call the increase of positive knowledge,
that of the latter is the elevation of the mind. Philosophy belongs to the latter category.
The view that the function of philosophy, especially metaphysics, is not the increase of positive
knowledge, is expounded by the Viennese school in contemporary Western philosophy, though from
a
different angle and for a different purpose. I do not agree with this school that the function of philoso
p
hy
is only the clarification of ideas, and that the nature of metaphysics is only a lyric of concepts.
N
evertheless, in their arguments one can see quite clearly that philosophy, especially metaphysics, would
become nonsense if it did attempt to give information regarding matters of fact.
Religion does give information in regard to matters of fact. But the information given by religion is
not in harmony with that given by science. So in the West there has been the conflict between religio
n
and science. Where science advances, religion retreats; and the authority of religion recedes before the
advancement of science. The traditionalists regretted this fact and pitied the people who had become
irreligious, considering them as having degenerated. They ought indeed to be pitied, if, besides religion,
they had no
OO8 THE SPIRIT OF CHINESE PHILOSOPHY
other access to the higher values. When people get rid of religion and have no substitute, they also lose
the higher values. They have to confine themselves to mundane affairs and have nothing to do with the
spiritual ones. Fortunately, however, besides religion there is philosophy,which provides man with an
access to the higher values—an access which is more direct than that provided by religion, because in
philosophy, in order to be acquainted with the higher values, man need not take the roundabout way
provided by prayers and rituals. The higher values with which man has become acquainted through
p
hilosophy are even purer than those acquired through religion, because they are not mixed wit
h
imagination and superstition. In the world of the future, man will have philosophy in the place o
f
religion. This is consistent with Chinese tradition. It is not necessary that man should be religious, but it
is necessary that he should be philosophical. When he is philosophical, he has the very best of the
blessings of religion.
P
roblem and Spirit of Chinese Philosophy
The above is a general discussion of the nature and function of philoso
p
hy. In the following remarks
I shall speak more specifically about Chinese philosophy. There is a main current in the history o
f
Chinese philosophy, which may be called the spirit of Chinese philosophy. In order to understand this
spirit, we must first make clear the problem that most Chinese philosophers have tried to solve.
There are all kinds and conditions of men. With regard to any one of these kinds, there is the highest
form of achievement of which any one kind of man is capable. For instance, there are the men engage
d
in practical politics. The highest form of achievement in that class of men is that of the great statesman.
So also in the field of art, the highest form of achievement of which artists are capable is that of the
great artist. Although there are these different classes of men, yet all of them are men. What is the
highest form of achievement of which a man as a man is capable? According to the Chinese
philosophers, it is nothing less than being a sage, and the highest achievement of a sage is the
identification of the individual with the universe. The problem is, if men want to achieve this
identification, do they necessarily have to abandon society or even to negate life?
According to some philosophers, this is necessary. The Buddha said that life itself is the root and
fountainhead of the misery of life. Likewise, Plato said that the body is the prison of the soul. And
some of the Taoists said that life is an excrescence, a tumor, and death is to be taken as the breaking o
f
the tumor. All these ideas represent a view which entails separation from what may be called the
entangling net of the matter-corrupted world; and therefore, if the highest achievement of a sage is to be
realized, the sage has to abandon society and even life itself. Only thus can the final liberation be
attained. This kind of philosophy is what is generally known as "other-
OIO THE SPIRIT OF CHINESE PHILOSOPHY
worldly philosophy.'
There is another kind of philosophy which emphasizes what is in society, such as human relations an
d
human affairs. This kind of philosophy speaks only about moral values, and is unable to or does not wish
to speak of the super-moral ones. This kind of philosophy is generally described as "this— worldly. Fro
m
the point of view of a this—worldly philosophy, an other — world philosophy is too idealistic, is of no
practical use and is negative. From the point of view of an other-worldly philosophy, a this-worl
d
philosophy is too realistic, too superficial. It may be positive,
b
ut it is like the quick walking of a ma
n
who has taken the wrong road: the more quickly he walks the further he goes astray.
There are many people who say that Chinese philosophy is a thisworld philosophy. It is difficult to
state that these people are entirely right or entirely wrong. Taking a merely superficial view, people who
hold this opinion cannot be said to be wrong, because according to their view, Chinese philosophy,
regardless of its different schools of thought, is directly or indirectly concerned with government an
d
ethics. On the surface, therefore, it is concerned chiefly with society, and not with the universe; with the
daily functions of human relations, not hell and heaven; with man's present life, but not his life in a world
to come. When he was once asked by a disciple about the meaning of death, Confucius replied:"Not ye
t
understanding life, how can you understand death? (Analects, XI, II.) And Mencius said: The sage is the
acme of human relations" (Mencius, IVa, 2.), which, taken literally, means that the sage is the morally
p
erfect man in society. From a surface point of view, with the ideal man being of this world, it seems tha
t
what Chinese philosophy calls a sage is a person of a very different order from the Buddha of Buddhis
m
and the saints of the Christian religion. Superficially, this would seem to be especially true of the
Confucian sage. That is why, in ancient times, Confucius and the Confucianists were so greatly ridicule
d
by the Taoists.
This, however, is only a surface view of the matter. Chinese philosophy cannot be understood by
oversimplification of this kind. So far as the main tenet of its tradition is concerned, if we understand i
t
aright, it cannot be said to be wholly this-worldly, just as, of course, it cannot be said to be wholly
other-worldly. Tt is both of this world and of the other world. Speaking about the Neo-Confucianism o
f
the Sung Dynasty, one philosopher described it this way: It is not divorced from daily ordinary activities,
摘要:

AUTHOR'SPREFACEASHORThistoryofanysubjectshouldnotsimplybeanabridgementofalargerone.Itshouldbeapicturecompleteinitself,ratherthanamereinventoryofnamesand"isms.'Toachievethis,theauthorshould,asaChineseexpressionsays,"havethewholehistoryinhismind.Onlythencanhegivethereaderanadequateandwell-roundedaccou...

展开>> 收起<<
冯友兰-中国哲学简史-英文原版.pdf

共232页,预览5页

还剩页未读, 继续阅读

声明:本站为文档C2C交易模式,即用户上传的文档直接被用户下载,本站只是中间服务平台,本站所有文档下载所得的收益归上传人(含作者)所有。玖贝云文库仅提供信息存储空间,仅对用户上传内容的表现方式做保护处理,对上载内容本身不做任何修改或编辑。若文档所含内容侵犯了您的版权或隐私,请立即通知玖贝云文库,我们立即给予删除!
分类:外语学习 价格:5.9玖币 属性:232 页 大小:1.23MB 格式:PDF 时间:2024-12-02

开通VIP享超值会员特权

  • 多端同步记录
  • 高速下载文档
  • 免费文档工具
  • 分享文档赚钱
  • 每日登录抽奖
  • 优质衍生服务
/ 232
客服
关注