4 FRÉDÉRIC LE ROUX AND MAXIME WOLFF
1.3. Ideas of the proof of Theorem 1.2. In the smooth case, the adaptation of
our proof of Theorem 1.1 fails from the start: indeed, the closed curves contained
in the union a∪b∪cof a necklace, and distinct from a,band c, are not smooth.
This suggests the idea to use sequences of curves (at the expense of losing the
characterizations of configurations in terms of first order logic).
This time it is easiest to first characterize disjointness of curves (see Lemma 5.7),
and then recover the different types of 3-cliques. Then the strategy follows the C0
case.
Once we start to work with sequences, it is natural to say that a sequence (fn)of
curves not escaping to infinity converges to ain some weak sense, if for every vertex
dsuch that {a, d}is an edge of the graph, {fn, d}is also an edge for all nlarge
enough. As it turns out, this property implies convergence in C0-sense to a, and
is implied by convergence in C1-sense. But it is not equivalent to the convergence
in C1-sense, and it is precisely this default of C1-convergence that enables us to
distinguish between disjoint or transverse pairs of curves.
Interestingly, this simple criterion for disjointness has no counterpart in the C0-
setting. Indeed, in that setting, no sequence of curves converges in this weak sense:
given a curve a, and a sequence (fn)of curves with, say, some accumulation point in
a, we can build a curve dintersecting aonce transversally (topologically), but oscil-
lating so much that it itersects every fnseveral times. From this perspective, none
of our approaches in the C0-setting and in the C∞-setting are directly adaptable to
the other.
1.4. Further comments. We can imagine many variants of fine graphs. For ex-
ample, in the arXiv version of [2], for the case of the torus they worked with the
graph NC†
⋔(Σ)on which we are working here, whereas in the published version,
they changed to a fine graph in which two curves aand bare still related by an edge
when they have one intersection, not necessarily transverse.
More generally, in the spirit of Ivanov’s metaconjecture, we expect that the group
of automorphisms should not change from any reasonable variant to another. And
indeed, using the ideas of [10, Section 2] and those presented here, we can navigate
between various versions of fine graphs, and recover, from elementary properties of
one version, the configurations defining the edges in another version, thus proving
that their automorphism groups are naturally isomorphic. From this perspective,
it seems satisfying to recover the group of homeomorphisms of the surface as the
automorphism group of any reasonable variant of the fine graph. In this vein,
we should mention that the results of [10, Section 2] directly yield a natural map
Aut(C†(Σ)) →Aut(NC†
⋔(Σ)), and from there, our proof of Theorem 1.1 may be
used as an alternative proof of their main result.
All reasonable variants of the fine graphs should be quasi-isometric, and a unifying
theorem (yet out of reach today, as it seems to us) would certainly be a counterpart
of the theorem by Rafi and Schleimer [13], which states that every quasi-isometry
of the usual curve graph is bounded distance from an isometry.
1.5. Organization of the article. Section 2 is devoted to the recognition of the
3-cliques in the C0-setting, and of some other configurations regarding the nonori-
entable case. We encourage the reader to skip, at first reading, everything that
concerns the nonorientable case: these points shoud be easily identified, and this
halves the length of the proof. In Section 3 we prove Theorem 1.1. In Section 4
we characterize, from the topological viewpoint, the relation yintroduced above in