Multi-utility representations of preferences over lotteries

2025-05-02 0 0 371.81KB 33 页 10玖币
侵权投诉
arXiv:2210.04739v2 [math.CA] 13 Jan 2024
EXPECTED MULTI-UTILITY REPRESENTATIONS OF
PREFERENCES OVER LOTTERIES
PAOLO LEONETTI
Abstract. Let %be a binary relation on the set of simple lotteries over a
countable outcome set Z. We provide necessary and sufficient conditions on
%to guarantee the existence of a set Uof von Neumann–Morgenstern utility
functions u:ZRsuch that
p%qEp[u]Eq[u]for all uU
for all simple lotteries p, q. In such case, the set Uis essentially unique. Then,
we show that the analogue characterization does not hold if Zis uncountable.
This provides an answer to an open question posed by Dubra, Maccheroni,
and Ok in [J. Econom. Theory 115 (2004), no. 1, 118–133]. Lastly, we show
that different continuity requirements on %allow for certain restrictions on the
possible choices of the set Uof utility functions (e.g., all utility functions are
bounded), providing a wide family of expected multi-utility representations.
1. Introduction
Let %be a binary relation on a topological space X. The classical Debreu’s
utility representation theorem provides sufficient conditions on %and Xfor the
existence of a continuous utility function u:XRwhich represents %, so that
x%yu(x)u(y),
for all x, y X. In such case, %is necessarily complete and transitive.
However, since the seminal works of Aumann [5] and Bewley [7], it is known
that completeness may not be considered a basic trait of rationality of the decision
maker. A long line of research studies this topic, see e.g. [9,14,18,34,35] and
2020 Mathematics Subject Classification. C79, D11.
Key words and phrases. Preferences over lotteries; closed convex cones; finitely-supported
probability measures; duality pairs; expected multi-utility representation.
2Paolo Leonetti
references therein. The main objective of this paper is to provide continuous multi-
utility representation theorems for preference relations over lotteries which may
fail to be complete. Thus, the basic question can be formulated as follows: Given
binary relation %on a sufficiently well-behaved topological space X, we search
for necessary and sufficient conditions on %for which there exists a collection U
of continuous utility functions u:XRsuch that
x%y⇒ ∀uU, u(x)u(y),
for all x, y X. Note that, in such case, the binary relation is necessarily reflexive
and transitive, hence a preorder. In addition, we may interpret %as resulting from
the unanimity of a family of complete preference relations, each one admitting a
classical Debreu’s continuous utility representation.
In many instances, the underlying space Xhas also the structure of (convex
subset of a) vector space, so that it makes sense to require each continuous utility
function uto be, in addition, linear. To make an example, in the important work
of Dubra, Maccheroni and Ok [14], the authors provide necessary and sufficient
conditions on a binary relation %over the set Pof Borel probability measures
on a compact metric space to satisfy the representation
p%q⇒ ∀uU, Ep[u]Eq[u],
for all p, q P. Moreover, the set Uis essentially unique, in a precise sense. The
interpretation of such representation is that the decision maker can show a lack
of confidence in the evaluation of lotteries because he is unsure about his future
tastes/risk attitudes, each represented by an utility function in U.
In the same work, the authors pose as open question in [14, Remark 1] whether
the analogue characterization holds replacing Pwith the set of simple lotteries
on a given outcome set Z. Hereafter, a simple lottery (or, simply, a lottery)
stands for a finitely-supported probability measure on Z.The main result of
this work is that the answer is affirmative if and only if Zis finite or countably
infinite. See Theorem 2.3 and Theorem 2.4 below for the positive and negative
case, respectively. Details follow in Section 2.
Our methods of proofs will be sufficiently strong to provide a wide family of
expected multi-utility representations. Indeed, we show that different continuity
Representations of preferences over lotteries 3
requirements on %allow for certain restrictions on the possible choices of the
utility functions (e.g., all utility functions are bounded, or countably supported).
Indeed, it is known that different continuity properties in an infinite dimensional
framework may correspond to different behavioral implications, see e.g. [16].
Lastly, removing also the transitivity and continuity requirements, we provide a
representation for reflexive binary relations %which satisfy the independence ax-
iom over lotteries on arbitrary outcome sets Z, in the same spirit of the coalitional
representation given by Hara, Ok, and Riella in [24, Theorem 1].
1.1. Motivations. Before we provide the details of our contribution, we remark
that there are several economic reasons why one should be interested in the study
of incomplete preference relations. Indeed, many authors strongly suggest, from
both the normative and positive viewpoints, that preference relations should allow
for potential indecisiveness of the decision makers, see e.g. [5,7]. Accordingly,
within the revealed preference paradigm, it has been recently shown that incom-
pleteness of preferences may arise due to status quo bias and the endowment
effect, see e.g. [15,33]. As an application, the resulting theory in [15] has been
able to cope with the classical preference reversal phenomenon.
In the case of our incomplete preferences, there are economic examples in which
a decision maker is in fact composed of several agents, each one with a given utility
function. For instance, in a social choice framework such as environmental policy,
healthcare, or public policy, one commonly uses the Pareto dominance to rank
alternatives (cf. First and Second Welfare Theorem), and such criterion is, of
course, incomplete. As another real-world example, when purchasing a car, one
needs to consider factors like price, fuel efficiency, safety, and style; here, the
decision maker has to compare preferences over these multiple criteria.
As anticipated before, we are going to study how to handle the problem of ac-
tually representing such preferences with expected multi-utility models as in [14].
It is worth to remark that the very same idea goes back at least to von Neumann
and Morgenstern, see [40, pp. 19–20], although without details. In this work, in
particular, we focus on preferences over simple lotteries (i.e., probability distri-
butions with finite support) on a given outcome set. There are many practical
4Paolo Leonetti
motivations which justify this choice (apart from answering an open question in
[14]), and we list below several ones.
First, simple lotteries provide a way to model and analyze situations involving
uncertainty and risk, cf. e.g. [8,13]. Accordingly, they can be considered as the
building blocks of utility theory, which is a cornerstone of microeconomics and
rational decision making. As remarked by Evren in [17], simple lotteries can also
be interpreted, in a game theory framework, as strategic decisions where players
and the nature are confined to play simple strategies.
Second, in various fields such as finance, engineering, and operations research,
problems involve decision variables that are inherently finite. Preferences over
probability distributions on these variables are essential, e.g., for optimation prob-
lems. Simple lotteries are also employed in portfolio theory to assess the risk and
return profiles of different investment portfolios. Diversification strategies, aimed
at reducing risk, rely on preferences over (asset) lotteries. Similarly, in policy
analysis and resource allocation problems, decision makers often have to make
choices that affect finite populations or groups. Representations of these pref-
erences help assess the impact of different policies on such finite groups. As a
last example, in surveys or experiments, responses often take on discrete values,
and the resulting probability distributions are finitely-supported. In this sense,
studying preferences on the latter distributions allows decision makers to directly
deal with the empirical data.
Third, simple lotteries are often easier to work with and understand than con-
tinuous ones. This simplicity can make it more feasible for individuals to express
and communicate their preferences over such distributions. In addition, if pref-
erences are not fully known or cannot be easily elicited, the study of incomplete
preferences on probability measures offers a practical approach. Indeed, decision
makers can express partial preferences over some aspects of a decision problem,
even when they are unsure about others.
Lastly, even if representations of such incomplete preferences may seem rather
technical, recent studies have shown that they are useful tools to understanding
certain classes of complete preferences. For example, the cautious expected util-
ity model by Cerreia-Vioglio, Dillenberger, and Ortoleva [10] can be derived by
applying the expected multi-utility representation of Dubra, Maccheroni, and Ok
Representations of preferences over lotteries 5
[14]. A similar remark holds for multi-prior expected multi-utility representations
due to Galaabaatar and Karni [20].
2. Preliminaries and Main results
Let be the set of finitely-supported probability measures on a given nonempty
set Z, which is interpreted as the set of lotteries over the set of possible outcomes
Z, see e.g. [10,12,22,23,29]. A utility function over Zis a real-valued map
u:ZR. Note that is a convex subset of the vector space of finitely-
supported functions p:ZR, hereafter denoted by RZ
0. Hence, a lottery is a
nonnegative function pRZ
0such that PzZp(z) = 1.
Definition 2.1. Let Zbe a nonempty set. A binary relation %on satisfies the
independence axiom if
p%qαp + (1 α)r%αq + (1 α)r(1)
for all lotteries p, q, r and scalars α(0,1).
Hereafter, for each pRZ
0and utility function u:ZR, define
Ep[u] := XzZu(z)p(z).
As anticipated in Section 1, our main objective is to characterize binary relations
%over lotteries through expected multi-utility representations in the sense of
Dubra, Maccheroni, and Ok [14], that is, to search for necessary and/or sufficient
conditions on %for which there exists a set Uof utility functions (possibly, of a
certain type) such that
p%q⇒ ∀uU, Ep[u]Eq[u],(2)
for all lotteries p, q .
To this aim, we endow the vector space RZ
0with the weak-topology
w:= σ(RZ
0,RZ),
so that a net (pi)iIweak-converges to some pRZ
0if and only if
(Epi[u])iIEp[u]for all uRZ.
Note that (RZ
0, w)is a locally convex Hausdorff topological vector space. Moreover,
we endow RZwith the weak-topology σ(RZ,RZ
0)which is, equivalently, the
摘要:

arXiv:2210.04739v2[math.CA]13Jan2024EXPECTEDMULTI-UTILITYREPRESENTATIONSOFPREFERENCESOVERLOTTERIESPAOLOLEONETTIAbstract.Let%beabinaryrelationonthesetofsimplelotteriesoveracountableoutcomesetZ.Weprovidenecessaryandsufficientconditionson%toguaranteetheexistenceofasetUofvonNeumann–Morgensternutilityfunct...

展开>> 收起<<
Multi-utility representations of preferences over lotteries.pdf

共33页,预览5页

还剩页未读, 继续阅读

声明:本站为文档C2C交易模式,即用户上传的文档直接被用户下载,本站只是中间服务平台,本站所有文档下载所得的收益归上传人(含作者)所有。玖贝云文库仅提供信息存储空间,仅对用户上传内容的表现方式做保护处理,对上载内容本身不做任何修改或编辑。若文档所含内容侵犯了您的版权或隐私,请立即通知玖贝云文库,我们立即给予删除!
分类:图书资源 价格:10玖币 属性:33 页 大小:371.81KB 格式:PDF 时间:2025-05-02

开通VIP享超值会员特权

  • 多端同步记录
  • 高速下载文档
  • 免费文档工具
  • 分享文档赚钱
  • 每日登录抽奖
  • 优质衍生服务
/ 33
客服
关注