Making Information More Valuable Mark Whitmeyer June 27 2024

2025-05-02 0 0 1.5MB 52 页 10玖币
侵权投诉
Making Information More Valuable
Mark Whitmeyer
June 27, 2024
Abstract
We study what changes to an agents decision problem increase her value for infor-
mation. We prove that information becomes more valuable if and only if the agents
reduced-form payoin her belief becomes more convex. When the transformation
corresponds to the addition of an action, the requisite increase in convexity occurs if
and only if a simple geometric condition holds, which extends in a natural way to the
addition of multiple actions. We apply these findings to two scenarios: a monopolistic
screening problem in which the good is information and delegation with information
acquisition.
Keywords: Expected Utility, Selling Information, Information Acquisition, Delegation
JEL Classifications: D81; D82; D83
Arizona State University. Email: mark.whitmeyer@gmail.com. I am grateful to Simon Board, Costas
Cavounidis, Gregorio Curello, Dana Foarta, Rosemary Hopcroft, Vasudha Jain, Doron Ravid, Eddie Schlee,
Ludvig Sinander, Bruno Strulovici, Can Urgun, Tong Wang, Joseph Whitmeyer, Tom Wiseman, Renkun
Yang, Kun Zhang, and various seminar and conference audiences for their feedback. I also thank the editor,
Emir Kamenica, and four anonymous referees for their useful suggestions. This paper was formerly titled
“Flexibility and Information.
1
arXiv:2210.04418v5 [econ.TH] 26 Jun 2024
When action grows unprofitable, gather information;
when information grows unprofitable, sleep.
Ursula Le Guin, The Left Hand of Darkness
1 Introduction
To a rational, expected-utility maximizing decision-maker, information is always valu-
able. However, some kinds of information are more valuable than others. Likewise, in-
formation is more valuable in certain decision problems than in others. The economics
literature, commencing with the seminal work of Blackwell (Blackwell (1951) and Black-
well (1953)), has largely focused on the first comparison, between information structures.
In this paper, we study the second comparison, between decision problems. When can
we say that one agent values information more than another? Equivalently, suppose we
alter an agents decision problem. What sorts of modifications increase her value for in-
formation?
Blackwell’s way of comparing information structures is relatively detail-free. In his
ranking, information structure 1 is more valuable than information structure 2 if for any
prior held by the agent and any decision problem, the agent prefers 1 to 2. In this paper,
in specifying what it means for agent 1 to value information more than agent 2, we take
a similarly broad approach. Namely, we require that any information structure be more
valuable to agent 1 than agent 2, no matter the prior.
We begin by identifying that relative convexity distinguishes agents’ comparative love
of information. Agent 1 values information more than agent 2 if the dierence in the
agents’ value functions1V1V2is convex. Next, we turn our attention to the value func-
tions themselves. What modifications to an agent’s decision problem result in an increase
in convexity? One natural way to alter an agent’s decision problem is by allowing her an
additional action. How does increased flexibility–a greater capacity to adapt her behavior
to new information–change an agent’s value for information?
1An agents value function, V(µ), is her maximal expected payoat any belief µ(Θ), obtained by
plugging in an optimizing action. We define this object formally on page 6 in Expression 1.
2
In §4.2, we carry this analysis further by allowing the agent not just one but potentially
multiple additional actions. Next, in §4.3, we remove actions. We then leave the set of
actions unchanged (§4.4), but instead scale the agent’s utility. This allows us to speak to
the eects of repetition and aggregate risk on the value of information. In §4.5, we reveal
that increased (or decreased) risk aversion has an ambiguous aect on an agents value
for information.
Central to our study is the observation that a modification to an agent’s decision prob-
lem alters her value for information through two channels. The first is the agent’s sen-
sitivity to information–if her value for information increases (in the manner defined in
this paper) it must be that she is more reactive to information. The second is the value
to the agent of distinguishing between actions. This must also increase if the agents
value for information is to increase. All in all, a transformation makes information more
valuable if and only if the agent becomes more sensitive to information and the value of
distinguishing between actions increases.
When the transformation to the decision problem is either the addition or subtraction
of actions, the first channel is all-important. This is particularly stark when we modify
the agents decision problem by adding a single action (§4.1): the agents value for infor-
mation increases if and only if she becomes more sensitive to information. We uncover a
simple geometric condition necessary and sucient for this to transpire and show that an
iterative version of this condition also guarantees an increase in the value of information
when multiple actions are added. Moreover, although this condition is not necessary to
make information more valuable when multiple actions are added, any failure of neces-
sity is not robust–perturbing the utilities from the new actions slightly will make it so
that the agent does not become more sensitive to information.
Perhaps unexpectedly, we discover that unless all of the remaining actions or all of
the removed actions were initially dominated, taking away actions can never lead to a
higher value for information. That is, it is only an elimination that results in a totally
new decision problem (in eect) or the exact same decision problem, that can lead to an
increase in an agents value for information. Any removal other than these necessarily
makes the agent less sensitive to information.
3
1.1 Motivating Example
The question under study has significant practical relevance. The job of a regulator is to
enact policies that modify the incentives of agents in some environment. This typically
entails the addition or subtraction of actions: there are contracts that an insurer may not
oer, assets that an investment firm may not sell, and limits to how many fish a trawler
may catch.2Insurers themselves change agents’ payos by reducing their risk, flattening
their payos. Firms do the opposite with their workers: bonus schemes tied to a worker’s
performance make her payosteeper and more sensitive to randomness.
Consider for instance an insurance provider dictating what treatments it will cover;
viz., what procedures a doctor may conduct. For simplicity, suppose there are three con-
ditions a patient with an injured hand may have–three states of the world. In one state,
state 0, the injury is just a sprain; in another, state 1, a bone is broken but not displaced;
and in state 2, the fracture is displaced.
Suppose first the doctor may only oer one treatment: place a cast on the hand (action
c). Accordingly, she has two possible actions, do nothing (action n), which is uniquely
optimal if the injury is just a sprain; or cast the hand, which is uniquely optimal if the
hand is broken. This decision problem is represented in Figure 1a: point (µ1,µ2)specifies
the respective probabilities (beliefs) that the bone is broken but not displaced or broken
and displaced. Accordingly, the blue region is the region of probabilities in which nis
optimal; and the red region are those probabilities for which cis optimal.
Let us now consider two possible new treatments aorded to the doctor. Suppose the
provider now covers surgery (action s). This is relatively high-risk and is only optimal if
the doctor is confident the bone is broken and displaced. Figure 1b represents this new
decision problem: sis optimal if and only if the doctor’s belief is in the purple region. On
the other hand, suppose the provider instead allows a conservative treatment consisting
of stretching and rehabilitating exercises (action r). This is better than nothing in the
case of a fracture, but is inferior to rest for sprains. This scenario is Figure 1c, where ris
2The verdicts that can be handed down in criminal cases are also legislated, so our results also speak to
what kinds of verdicts improve incentives for information acquisition (cf. Siegel and Strulovici (2020)).
4
optimal for beliefs in the black region.
Which of these new options, if either, does not dampen the doctor’s enthusiasm for
information, regardless of her prior or what that information may be? As we discover in
this paper, the answer is simple, only the former of the two potential new procedures,
surgery, makes information more valuable. Indeed, suppose that a sprain and a break
are equally likely. With only the initial two treatments to choose from, the doctor strictly
benefits from any information. If we gave the doctor the conservative option, this would
clearly no longer be true: any information that doesnt move her beliefs much is now
worthless, as the conservative treatment remains optimal at those beliefs. In contrast, the
surgery option makes information weakly more valuable.
The crucial dierence between the two potential new actions is that the surgery option
is refining: only the region of beliefs in which doing nothing is optimal shrinks. In
contrast, the conservative treatment partially replaces each pre-existing treatment.
2 The Model
There is a grand set of actions A. Our protagonist is a decision-maker, an agent who
initially possesses a compact set of actions AA. There is an unknown state of the
world θ, which is drawn according to some full-support prior µ0from some finite set of
states Θ. Initially, the agent has some continuous utility function u:A×ΘR.
DB(u,A,Θ)denotes the agents Initial Decision Problem. We are studying the eect
of a transformation of the decision problem on the agents value for information.3To
that end, ˆ
DBˆ
u, ˆ
A,Θdenotes the agents Transformed Decision Problem. Here are a few
leading examples of such transformations:
Scenario 1. Becoming More Flexible. Ais finite. In ˆ
D, the agents utility function re-
mains unchanged, ˆ
u=u; and her new set of actions is ˆ
ABABfor some additional finite
set of actions BA\A.
Scenario 2. Becoming A Little More Flexible. This is the special case of the agent be-
3Equivalently, we are comparing two dierent agents’ values for information.
5
摘要:

MakingInformationMoreValuableMarkWhitmeyer∗June27,2024AbstractWestudywhatchangestoanagent’sdecisionproblemincreasehervalueforinfor-mation.Weprovethatinformationbecomesmorevaluableifandonlyiftheagent’sreduced-formpayoffinherbeliefbecomesmoreconvex.Whenthetransformationcorrespondstotheadditionofanacti...

展开>> 收起<<
Making Information More Valuable Mark Whitmeyer June 27 2024.pdf

共52页,预览5页

还剩页未读, 继续阅读

声明:本站为文档C2C交易模式,即用户上传的文档直接被用户下载,本站只是中间服务平台,本站所有文档下载所得的收益归上传人(含作者)所有。玖贝云文库仅提供信息存储空间,仅对用户上传内容的表现方式做保护处理,对上载内容本身不做任何修改或编辑。若文档所含内容侵犯了您的版权或隐私,请立即通知玖贝云文库,我们立即给予删除!
分类:图书资源 价格:10玖币 属性:52 页 大小:1.5MB 格式:PDF 时间:2025-05-02

开通VIP享超值会员特权

  • 多端同步记录
  • 高速下载文档
  • 免费文档工具
  • 分享文档赚钱
  • 每日登录抽奖
  • 优质衍生服务
/ 52
客服
关注