
v PREFACE
reader, of course, is not obliged to share the political views of the author, which the latter
on his side has no reason to conceal. But the reader does have the right to demand that a his-
torical work should not be the defence of a political position, but an internally well-founded
portrayal of the actual process of the revolution. A historical work only then completely
fulfils the mission when events unfold upon its pages in their full natural necessity.
For this, is it necessary to have the so-called historian’s “impartiality”? Nobody has yet
clearly explained what this impartiality consists of. The often quoted words of Clmenceau
that it is necessary to take a revolution “en bloc,” as a whole are at the best a clever evasion.
How can you take as a whole a thing whose essence consists in a split? Clmenceaus apho-
rism was dictated partly by shame for his too resolute ancestors, partly by embarrassment
before their shades.
One of the reactionary and therefore fashionable historians in contemporary France, L.
Madelin, slandering in his drawing-room fashion the great revolution that is, the birth of his
own nation asserts that “the historian ought to stand upon the wall of a threatened city, and
behold at the same time the besiegers and the besieged”: only in this way, it seems, can he
achieve a “conciliatory justice.” However, the words of Madelin himself testify that if he
climbs out on the wall dividing the two camps, it is only in the character of a reconnoiterer
for the reaction. It is well that he is concerned only with war camps of the past: in a time
of revolution standing on the wall involves great danger. Moreover, in times of alarm the
priests of “conciliatory justice” are usually found sitting on the inside of four walls waiting
to see which side will win.
The serious and critical reader will not want a treacherous impartiality, which offers him
a cup of conciliation with a well-settled poison of reactionary hate at the bottom, but a sci-
entific conscientiousness, which for its sympathies and antipathies open and undisguised
seeks support in an honest study of the facts, a determination of their real connections, an
exposure of the causal laws of their movement. That is the only possible historic objec-
tivism, and moreover it is amply sufficient, for it is verified and attested not by the good
intentions of the historian, for which only he himself can vouch, but the natural laws re-
vealed by him of the historic process itself.
The sources of this book are innumerable periodical publications, newspapers and jour-
nals, memoirs, reports, and other material, partly in manuscript, but the greater part pub-
lished by the Institute of the History of the Revolution in Moscow and Leningrad. We have
considered its superfluous to make reference in the text to particular publications, since
that would only bother the reader. Among the books which have the character of collec-
tive historical works we have particularly used the two-volume Essays on the History of
the October Revolution (Moscow-Leningrad, 1927). Written by different authors, the var-
ious parts of this book are unequal in value, but they contain at any rate abundant factual