Quantifying Quantum Causal Influences Lucas Hutter1Rafael Chaves23Ranieri Vieira Nery2George Moreno24and Daniel Jost Brod1 1Institute of Physics Federal University Fluminense Niter oi Brazil

2025-05-02 0 0 3.56MB 12 页 10玖币
侵权投诉
Quantifying Quantum Causal Influences
Lucas Hutter,1Rafael Chaves,2,3Ranieri Vieira Nery,2George Moreno,2,4and Daniel Jost Brod1
1Institute of Physics, Federal University Fluminense, Niter´
oi, Brazil
2International Institute of Physics, Federal University of Rio Grande do Norte, 59070-405 Natal, Brazil
3School of Science and Technology, Federal University of Rio Grande do Norte, 59078-970 Natal, Brazil
4Departamento de Computac¸˜
ao, Universidade Federal Rural de Pernambuco, 52171-900, Recife, Pernambuco, Brazil
Causal influences are at the core of any empirical science, the reason why its quantification is of
paramount relevance for the mathematical theory of causality and applications. Quantum correla-
tions, however, challenge our notion of cause and effect, implying that tools and concepts developed
over the years having in mind a classical world, have to be reevaluated in the presence of quantum
effects. Here, we propose the quantum version of the most common causality quantifier, the average
causal effect (ACE), measuring how much a target quantum system is changed by interventions on
its presumed cause. Not only it offers an innate manner to quantify causation in two-qubit gates but
also in alternative quantum computation models such as the measurement-based version, suggest-
ing that causality can be used as a proxy for optimizing quantum algorithms. Considering quantum
teleportation, we show that any pure entangled state offers an advantage in terms of causal effects as
compared to separable states. This broadness of different uses showcases that, just as in the classical
case, the quantification of causal influence has foundational and applied consequences and can lead
to a yet totally unexplored tool for quantum information science.
In spite of the mantra in statistics that ”correlation
does not imply causation”, a central goal of any quanti-
tative science is precisely that: to infer cause and effect
relations from observed data [1,2]. In fact, as stated by
Reichenbach’s principle [3], correlations between two
events do imply some causation. Either one has a direct
influence over the other or a third event acts as a com-
mon cause for both of them. Within this context, given
variables Aand B, the basic aim of causal inference is
to distinguish how much of their observed correlations
are due to direct causal influences, rather than due to
a potential common cause Λ. However, if we do not
have empirical access to Λ, which is then treated as a la-
tent/hidden variable, both models—common cause or
direct causal influences—generate the same set of pos-
sible correlations that cannot be set apart from obser-
vations alone. With that aim, one has to rely on inter-
ventions [1]. By intervening on A, we fix it to a value
independent of Λsuch that any remaining correlations
between Aand Bcan unambiguously be traced back to
a direct influence AB, a fundamental result with a
wide range of applications [49].
Notwithstanding all the successes of causality the-
ory, since Bell’s theorem [10] it is known that the clas-
sical notions of cause and effect break down at the
quantum level. Not only the notion of a causal struc-
ture has to be generalized in order to include quan-
tum states [1118] or the possibility of superposition of
causal orders [1921]; but also the meaning and appli-
cability of Bell inequalities as a causal compatibility tool
[22] have to be reevaluated [23], and tests employed to
bound the causal effects [24] have to be readjusted [25].
Given that, a fundamental question reemerges: how
can we quantify quantum causal effects? Complemen-
tary frameworks for reasoning about quantum causal
influences have been developed [13,15,17,20,21] and
explicit quantifiers of causality have already been pro-
posed [26,27]. Nevertheless, the quantum generaliza-
tion of the most widely used and intuitive quantifier
of causality in the classical case, the so-called average
causal effect (ACE) [1,7,24,25,28,29], has not yet been
achieved. That is the main goal of this Letter.
Using the trace distance, we propose a quantum ver-
sion of the ACE. It quantifies the causal influence that
an intervention on a system might have on a result-
ing quantum state. We show the applicability of our
framework in a number of paradigmatic quantum in-
formation scenarios. We start quantifying causal in-
fluences in two-qubit gates and discussing the advan-
tages of our approach as compared to other recent pro-
posals [26]. Within the context of measurement-based
quantum computation [30,31] and quantum teleporta-
tion [32], we show that separable states imply a limited
amount of causal influence, a restraint that can be sur-
passed by any pure entangled state. Thus, our quantum
causality quantifier not only provides a natural exten-
sion of a widely used and acknowledged classical tool
but also can be seen as a novel witness of non-classical
behavior.
Quantum Average Causal Effect – Suppose we ob-
serve correlations between variables Aand B, that
is, their probability distribution does not factorize as
p(a,b)6=p(a)p(b). From Reichenbach’s principle [3],
the most general causal model explaining such correla-
tions might involve direct influences as well as a com-
mon cause Λthat, for a variety of reasons, might not be
arXiv:2210.04306v1 [quant-ph] 9 Oct 2022
2
directly observed. Thus, at least in a classical descrip-
tion, the conditional observational distribution p(b|a)
can be decomposed as
p(b|a) =
λ
p(λ|a)p(b|a,λ). (1)
If, however, an intervention is performed on A, an op-
eration denoted as do(a), the interventional distribution
is now
p(b|do(a)) =
λ
p(λ)p(b|a,λ), (2)
where p(b|do(a)) denotes the probability of bwhen
variable Ais set by force to be a, that is, any potential
influence it might have had from the common cause Λ
is erased. Importantly, interventions bring in a natu-
ral way for quantifying causality. For instance, if aand
bare binary variables, a widely used quantifier of the
causal influence from Ato B, the average causal effect
(ACE) [1,7,24,25,28,29], is defined as
ACE =|P(b1|do(a1)) P(b1|do(a0))|, (3)
measuring the change in the distribution p(b1) = p(b=
1)of the variable Bdepending whether the value of A
is set to a=1 or a=0. Notice that
P(b1|do(a1)) P(b1|do(a0)) = P(b0|do(a0)) P(b0|do(a1)),
therefore Eq. (3) accounts for the influence Aon the
full probability distribution of values of B. In contrast,
when Aand Bcan assume more than two values, gen-
eralizations of Eq. (3) are not unique.
For simplicity, first assume that only Bcan have more
than two values. If we want to measure the largest
causal influence Ahas over B, a natural generalization
is to maximize the right-hand side of Eq. (3) over all
values of b[25], such that
ACEmax =max
b|P(b|do(a1)) P(b|do(a0))|. (4)
This definition, however, might not capture the full
causal influence from Ato B, if that influence is very
spread through the event space of B. To illustrate, sup-
pose that Bcan assume integer values from 1 to 2N.
If a=0 (resp. a=1), the probability distribution
over Bis the uniform distribution over integers from
1to N(resp. N+1 to 2N). The ACE, as defined by
Eq. (4), decreases as Nincreases. And yet, changing
the value of Aclearly has a large effect on the distribu-
tion of B. This example illustrates the extent to which
ACEmax is sensitive to a coarse-graining of the prob-
ability distribution. Since our intention is to quantify
causal influence in quantum protocols, it makes sense
to allow for arbitrary coarse-grainings on outcomes of
quantum measurements—after all, we can always en-
code a coarse-graining strategy as degeneracies in the
measured observable.
Building on that, we propose a generalization of
Eq. (3) based on the well-know total variation distance
(TVD), the largest possible difference that the two dis-
tributions can assign to the same event, given by
δ(P,Q) = 1
2
xX|P(x)Q(x)|, (5)
where Pand Qare two probability distributions over
X. The ACE can then be defined as
ACETVD =1
2
b|P(b|do(a1)) P(b|do(a0))|. (6)
While it reduces to Eq. (3) when Bis binary, it actually
returns the largest value of ACEmax over all possible
coarse-grainings of the distribution of B.
To generalize Eq. (6) for a quantum system, there are
two choices. The first is to suppose we have some set of
possible measurement bases and compute the ACETVD
at the level of the probability distribution over mea-
surement outcomes in these bases. Often, this is desir-
able, since it operates directly at the level of outcomes
[23,25,33]—the success probability of a quantum game
or protocol might be stated in terms of these quantities,
as typically done within device-independent quantum
information [34]. However, there are in principle in-
finitely many choices of measurement bases, and differ-
ent protocols or setups can differ on how much infor-
mation the experimenter or measuring agent has over
which bases they should measure. Therefore, it can also
be meaningful to measure directly the causal influence
of a parent variable on the resulting quantum state, ag-
nostic to which basis (if any) it will be measured in.
Following this reasoning, we propose a generaliza-
tion of the ACE for quantum states in terms of the trace
distance (TD), a well-known generalization of the TVD
measuring the distance between two density matrices ρ
and σ, defined as
TD(ρ,σ):=1
2Tr q(ρσ)2=1
2
i|λi|, (7)
where λiare the eigenvalues of the matrix (ρσ). Just
like the TVD accounts for all classical “strategies” (i.e.
choices of coarse-graining), the TD accounts for all pos-
sible quantum strategies. More concretely, the trace
distance between two states corresponds to the max-
imum TVD between the two probability distributions
that would arise from measuring those states with the
same POVM.
3
If Ais a classical binary variable, then the quantum
ACE is naturally defined as
ACEQ=TD(ρB(do(a1)),ρB(do(a0)), (8)
where ρB(do(a0)) is the density matrix that describes
the state at Bgiven the intervention do(a0). In many
cases, however, and particularly for the applications we
consider later on, Aactually corresponds to some pure
(qubit) quantum state. More concretely, Acould corre-
spond to any state in the Bloch sphere, and so Eq. (8) is
no longer well defined. We thus generalize it as follows
ACEQ=E
a0,a1
TD(ρB(do(a1)),ρB(do(a0)), (9)
where we now average over the choice of a0and a1.
Following [13], do-interventions on quantum states are
obtained simply by tracing whatever state represents A
and replacing it with a pure state, and subsequently
averaging over all possible states of A. Clearly, which
average must be performed depends on the nature of
the variable A. For instance, if it is an arbitrary state
in the Bloch sphere, the natural choice is the uniform
(Haar) distribution [35,36].
Causal influences in two-qubit gates– We consider a
two-qubit gate, U, acting on a pair of qubits labelled A
and B. We wish to compute the ACEQfrom the input
state of qubit Aonto the output of qubit B. We consider
that this gate might be embedded into a larger quantum
circuit, but that we perform a do-intervention on qubit
A, replacing it by some pure state |Ai[13]. As there is
no reason for Bto be diagonal in any particular basis,
we perform a Haar-random average over the input of
B. As we are also not interested in the output of qubit
A, it is traced out after the application of U. The entire
procedure, shown in Figure 1, can be summarized by
ACEQ(U) = E
|ai
E
|biTD(ρ(b|do(a),ρ(b|do(a)), (10)
where we used the shorthand
ρ(b|do(a)) = trAU|a,biha,b|U. (11)
The average over choices of intervention is done as
follows. First, we choose some state |ai, and assume the
intervention consisted of choosing either of the antipo-
dal states in the Bloch sphere |aiand a. We then av-
erage the result uniformly over |ai. We could have cho-
sen to average uniformly over two independent choices
of states |a0iand |a1i. However, this is computationally
more costly and seems to lead simply to a reduction
by a constant multiplicative factor. It is also intuitive
that, given any state |ai, the largest influence over Bis
obtained by choosing between either |aiand a.
FIG. 1. The setup used to calculate the causal influence of
quantum gates. Here the influence is measured from the entry
|aito the output of |bi(red lines). We perform a Haar-random
average over |biand a partial trace over the first output qubit.
Gate ACEQ
Local 0
cnot π/8
cz π/8
Bgate 0.5878
swap 0.6427
swap 1
TABLE I. ACEQ(U)for some noteworthy two-qubit gates. As
expected, the causal influence on a cnot gate is the same in
both directions. The Bgate was defined in [37], and is an
optimal two-qubit gate in the sense that any other gate can be
decomposed using only two copies of it (compared to three
cnot gates). This distinction manifests in the fact that ACEQ
is much larger for the Bgate than for the cnot
Our results, for a few paradigmatic quantum gates,
are summarized in Table Iand detailed in the Supple-
mental Material [38]. It is natural that the swap gate
displays the largest possible value of causal influence:
if the states of qubits Aand Bget swapped, then A
has maximal influence over Birrespective of anything
else. Another virtue of our definition is that it is basis
invariant. As a consequence, consider the cnot gate:
it flips the target qubit if the control qubit is in the
|1istate, and does nothing otherwise. Thus, one can
imagine that the influence only exists from the (input)
control qubit onto the (output) target qubit, or at least
that it is stronger in that direction. Our measure, how-
ever, attributes the same causal influence from the con-
trol to the target in a cnot gate as vice-versa, which
is to be expected since these roles can be flipped by a
local change of basis. Finally, our definition has a nat-
ural scale, ranging from 0(for local gates) to 1(for the
swap gate). Thus, not only our causality measure has
a fundamental motivation since it is a generalization of
the well-known ACE [1], it also displays a number of
advantages that can be showcased by comparison with
another recent proposal [26]. There, the cnot gate does
not have the same value of causal influence in both di-
rections, and neither does their definition has a natural
scale, which is inferred by averaging over Haar-random
摘要:

QuantifyingQuantumCausalInuencesLucasHutter,1RafaelChaves,2,3RanieriVieiraNery,2GeorgeMoreno,2,4andDanielJostBrod11InstituteofPhysics,FederalUniversityFluminense,Niter´oi,Brazil2InternationalInstituteofPhysics,FederalUniversityofRioGrandedoNorte,59070-405Natal,Brazil3SchoolofScienceandTechnology,Fe...

展开>> 收起<<
Quantifying Quantum Causal Influences Lucas Hutter1Rafael Chaves23Ranieri Vieira Nery2George Moreno24and Daniel Jost Brod1 1Institute of Physics Federal University Fluminense Niter oi Brazil.pdf

共12页,预览3页

还剩页未读, 继续阅读

声明:本站为文档C2C交易模式,即用户上传的文档直接被用户下载,本站只是中间服务平台,本站所有文档下载所得的收益归上传人(含作者)所有。玖贝云文库仅提供信息存储空间,仅对用户上传内容的表现方式做保护处理,对上载内容本身不做任何修改或编辑。若文档所含内容侵犯了您的版权或隐私,请立即通知玖贝云文库,我们立即给予删除!
分类:图书资源 价格:10玖币 属性:12 页 大小:3.56MB 格式:PDF 时间:2025-05-02

开通VIP享超值会员特权

  • 多端同步记录
  • 高速下载文档
  • 免费文档工具
  • 分享文档赚钱
  • 每日登录抽奖
  • 优质衍生服务
/ 12
客服
关注