Mathematical definition of public language and modeling of will and consciousness based on the public language Hana H ebishima Mina Arakaki Chikako Dozono Hanna Frolova Shinichi Inage

2025-05-02 0 0 1.09MB 21 页 10玖币
侵权投诉
Mathematical definition of public language, and modeling of will and consciousness
based on the public language
Hana Hebishima, Mina Arakaki, Chikako Dozono, Hanna Frolova, Shinichi Inage
To propose a mathematical model of consciousness and will, we first simulated the inverted qualia
with a toy model of a neural network. As a result, we confirmed that there can be an inverted qualia
on the neural network. In other words, the qualia were individual-dependent and considered difficult
as an indicator of consciousness and will. To solve that difficulty, we introduce a probability space and
a random variable into a set of qualia and define a public language for events. Based on this idea of
public language, consciousness and will are modeled. In this proposal, future actions are randomly
selected from the comparison between "recognition of events" by external observation and past
episodic memory, and the actual "recognition of actions" is regarded as the occurrence of consciousness.
The basic formula is also derived. This proposal is compared with other past philosophical discussions.
Key words: conscious, will, mathematical model, probability space, information entropy
1. Introduction
This paper is concerned with the mathematical definition of public language and the model of
consciousness derived from it. Modeling of consciousness is an important topic, and the relationship
between the conscious realm and its physical realm has been studied and developed over the centuries,
involving not only scientists but also philosophers and theologians (Bill Faw, 2014). Examples of
models of consciousness include the Global Workspace Theory (Stanislas Dehaene et al., 1998),
Multiple Draft Theory (Daniel C Dennett, 1993), Higher Thought Theory (Peter Carruthers, 2016),
Dehaene - Changeux model (Dehaene S, Changeux JP, 2000), Integrated Information Theory (Tononi
G, 2004, Masafumi Oizumi aet al., 2014) and many others. There are also many good reviews of those
models (Leonid I. Perlovsky, 2006, Christopher Durugbo et al., 2013), and we won't be introducing
each model sequentially here.
Among those theories, the integrated information theory was proposed by Tononi to quantify
consciousness - especially using the concept of information in information theory. The main purpose
of the program is to quantitatively evaluate the perception of a person as a first-person. Integrated
information theory does not keep in mind the so-called "hard problem of consciousness" but starts
from "consciousness exists" and adopts "information," "integration," "structure" and "exclusion" as
axioms. This system of theories is also of great interest, especially in terms of quantifying the
functions that complex networks produce. The basic concept is that consciousness appears when much
information is integrated, and the degree of integration is expressed by the integrated information
quantity:Φ. The Φ is defined for a set of variables that interact and evolve over time, and is a
quantification of how much more information the entire original network produces compared to the
sum of the information produced by the subnetworks that divided the network. For quantification,
we use the concept of KullbackLeibler divergence, which is also used in this paper.
These many models of consciousness complement metaphysical theories of consciousness, such
as functionalism, identity theory, dialogic dualism, and neutral monism. The following is a summary
of the topics related to this paper.
1.1 Qualia
"A unique texture that cannot be explained by words felt by each individual, caused by subjective
experiences and senses" is qualia. Even if we express our thoughts and feelings in words, they are
essentially things only we can know. For example, let's say a person gets a "bad vibe" when they see
a particular color. It is impossible to communicate and share that specific "bad feeling" with others by
any means. And a hideous color for one person may be a favorable color for another. However, while
we can explain why it is preferable, we cannot verbalize how it is preferable. In other words, because
qualia refer to the very feeling of everyone, it is impossible for others to feel qualia generated within
them in the same way.
Qualia is told with the following two characteristics.
1) Qualia is a subjective feeling gained through individual experience and the difficulty of verbalizing
everything correctly
2) Qualia are extremely personal and subjective and cannot be shared with others, and even if we go
through the same experience, the qualia we gain is incomprehensible to others
Thus, all sensations take place in an individual's brain and do not achieve the exact same qualia
as others.
1.2 Philosophical Zombies
The "philosophical zombie" is a thought experiment designed to counter the physicalism of
qualia and perceptions of consciousness. used by Chalmers, D., to describe qualia (Chalmers, D., 1996).
A philosophical zombie is a thought experiment defined as "a being who behaves like a normal human
being but in fact has no inner feelings." A major characteristic of philosophical zombies is the lack of
qualia. For a philosophical zombie, all emotions and sensations are just part of a brain activity. To put
it simply, a philosophical zombie is an entity that has sensations and emotions as a function but no
sensations and emotions as a reality. Philosophical zombies are said to be unrecognizable because
they look and behave no differently from humans. This is because, as mentioned above, qualia refer
to "the sensations and emotions felt by an individual," and it is impossible to prove whether the other
person has qualia. If it exists but can't be recognized, no one can prove it.
Physicism for consciousness is a monism that ascribes all phenomena to physics. The position is
that the human mind and senses fluctuate due to some physical phenomenon and can be observed as
an activity of the brain, and for this reason, in physicalism, the human mind and qualia are also
regarded as "physical objects."
An opposing position is the dualistic idea that there are objects that can be physically observed
and objects that cannot be physically observed. Even if we try to physically analyze emotions and
sensations, what we can observe is the physical phenomena of the brain, and we can't observe whether
there is "something" other than the physical phenomena of the brain. This leads to the idea that the
essence of the human mind and consciousness cannot be expressed in modern physics, and this is
called the "hard problem of consciousness."
In physicalism, the "mind," such as consciousness and qualia, is taken as a physical phenomenon
of the brain - that is, "the mind is the same as the senses and emotions as functions." If physicalism
is right, we can say that philosophical zombies are unimaginable and "improbable." Physicism,
however, cannot prove why philosophical zombies are improbable, because the physical phenomena
of the brain do not explain why or how the mind arises. Based on this logic, the argument is that
"Physicism is wrong if philosophical zombies are imaginable, and their existence cannot be denied."
1.3 Inverted qualia
Consider, for example, the color red. Observers watching the same sunset: Even if A and B each
recognize the color of the sunset as "red," they cannot confirm whether the private "red" that A and B
recognize is the same. For example, even if A's perceived "red" is considered "blue for A" to B, there is
no problem with A and B's claim that "the setting sun is red." This "inverted qualia" thought
experiment argues that the idea of physicalism cannot explain differences in internal experiences,
such as the appearance and perception of colors among observers.
1.4 Existence of free will
B. Rivett attached a device that measured brain electrical signals to participants in the
experiment and had them move their wrists freely to measure brain electrical signals at that time (B.
Rivet, 1980). When we move our bodies, it is known that electrical signals, commands to move our
muscles, come out of our brains shortly before we move. The results of the experiment were in the
following order.
1)The brain produces electrical signals to move the wrist
2)Conscious to move the wrist
3)Wrist moves
This means that the brain is sending electrical signals to move the wrist before the person is
conscious of moving the wrist, and the wrist is already set to move before the person is conscious of
moving the wrist. In other words, the wrists did not move because he was conscious of moving them.
The normal human feeling that the wrist has moved because he or she wanted to move the wrist by
his or her own will is an "illusion," and before that will, the wrist has been determined to move by
something unconscious, and the command is coming out of the brain unconsciously. In the middle of
the process of moving the wrist, it is a state in which the conscious mind is aware in the pursuit of
"let's move." B. Rivet, between 2) and 3) above, there is a short time left for refusing to move the wrist,
within which man can stop the action at his own will. So, he concludes that human beings have free
will. However, there is no harm in interpreting the results of this experiment by thinking that it is
"consciousness" - i.e., that there is no free will - to recognize the results of unconscious random
processing in the brain as an afterthought. B. Rivet's interpretation of the experiment has been
criticized by dualistic interpreters and others. However, if we take the view of "consciousness" in the
absence of free will, we can assume that the brain unconsciously and randomly processes certain
options based on physicalism. If we consider the post-processing recognition at the stage when the
processing is determined to be "consciousness," we believe that it does not go against physicalism and
does not cause a "hard problem of consciousness.". In dualism, apart from physical phenomena, there
is non-physical "consciousness" that cannot be measured by physics. However, it fails to explain why
and how non-physical consciousness can influence our behavior and the processing of the brain, which
is a physical phenomenon. If consciousness, which is non-physical, can affect physics, we must also
consider the existence of so-called "telekinesis" and the possibility of consciousness in all things, which
seems to make interpretation more complicated.
1.5 Isolated Brains
Isolated brain is a condition in which the corpus callosum connecting the left and right sides of
the brain is removed for the purpose of treating epilepsy, etc. This prevents information from being
exchanged between the left and right sides of the brain. The left side of the brain is primarily
responsible for language areas, while the right side is responsible for imaging areas. If we ask a
subject with a separate brain, showing the subject only to his right eye, which is processed by his left
brain, "What is it?" he can tell. Conversely, if the left eye, which connects to the right side of the brain,
is seen alone, the right side of the brain, which connects to the right side of the brain, answers "I can't
see anything" because it can't process language. On the other hand, if we let him draw a picture of
the subject, his right brain, which controls the image area, can draw without any problem. It is
sometimes said that this separate brain subject has two personalities = consciousness. Considering
this, we think that consciousness is physically dominated, or at least influenced, by the physical state
of the brain.
1.6 Short-term and Long-term Memory
Memories are divided into short-term and long-term memories because of differences in their
temporal duration. Tulving further subdivides this long-term memory into "episodic" and "semantic"
memories. "Episodic memory" is a memory of a personal experience associated with a specific time
and place, and "semantic memory" is defined as a memory unrelated to a specific time and place
(Tulving, 1976). As a classification of long-term memory, "episodic memory" and "semantic memory"
may be combined into "declarative memory" and classified into two separately defined categories of
"procedural memory" (Squire, 1987). Procedural memory, for example, is said to be the memory of
how to ride a bicycle.
FIG. 1: Neural Network Configuration
Table 1: Color representation by RBG
No.
Reference colors
R
G
B
1
Red
255
0
0
2
Green
0
255
0
3
Blue
0
0
255
4
White
255
255
255
5
Black
0
0
0
Table 2: Learning results when Table 1 is used as input and output teacher signals
No.
Simulated Colors
Input
Output
R
G
B
1
Red
229
33
36
2
Green
38
227
38
3
Blue
38
39
231
4
White
254
255
253
5
Black
0
0
0
Table 3: Learning results considering color weakness
No.
Simulated Colors
Input
Output
R
G
B
1
Red
124
128
17
2
Green
124
115
18
3
Blue
185
202
255
4
White
255
255
255
5
Black
2
2
1
Table 4: Learning results when complementary colors in Table 1
are used as teacher signals for output
No.
Simulated Colors
Input
Output
R
G
B
1
Red
29
238
70
2
Green
245
17
62
3
Blue
236
161
32
4
White
255
255
255
5
Black
2
1
0
FIG 2: Comparison of neural network weight coefficients
Many existing models of consciousness seem to focus on first-person consciousness. In this paper,
we first think of the neutral network as a Toy Model of a brain, and we performed a simulation of the
inverted qualia using it. As a result, we show that color blindness and inverted qualia can occur even
in the same network structure only with different values and arrangements of coefficients. On that
basis, we defined second-person consciousness - especially qualia - mathematically and used the
results as axioms to examine the process of creating a physically possible consciousness. We aim to
build a model that can provide some answers to the above 1.11.6 questions. Here are the details:
2.Mathematical definitions and modeling of consciousness
2.1 Simulations of Inverted qualia
The possibility of 'inverted qualia' mentioned in the introduction is explored through a
simulation based on a neural network. Neural networks, a type of machine learning that mimics the
function of neurons in the brain, have many applications and achievements as so-called artificial
intelligence. Now consider the three primary colors of red (R), green (G) and blue (B) and the five
摘要:

Mathematicaldefinitionofpubliclanguage,andmodelingofwillandconsciousnessbasedonthepubliclanguageHanaHebishima,MinaArakaki,ChikakoDozono,HannaFrolova,ShinichiInageToproposeamathematicalmodelofconsciousnessandwill,wefirstsimulatedtheinvertedqualiawithatoymodelofaneuralnetwork.Asaresult,weconfirmedthat...

展开>> 收起<<
Mathematical definition of public language and modeling of will and consciousness based on the public language Hana H ebishima Mina Arakaki Chikako Dozono Hanna Frolova Shinichi Inage.pdf

共21页,预览5页

还剩页未读, 继续阅读

声明:本站为文档C2C交易模式,即用户上传的文档直接被用户下载,本站只是中间服务平台,本站所有文档下载所得的收益归上传人(含作者)所有。玖贝云文库仅提供信息存储空间,仅对用户上传内容的表现方式做保护处理,对上载内容本身不做任何修改或编辑。若文档所含内容侵犯了您的版权或隐私,请立即通知玖贝云文库,我们立即给予删除!
分类:图书资源 价格:10玖币 属性:21 页 大小:1.09MB 格式:PDF 时间:2025-05-02

开通VIP享超值会员特权

  • 多端同步记录
  • 高速下载文档
  • 免费文档工具
  • 分享文档赚钱
  • 每日登录抽奖
  • 优质衍生服务
/ 21
客服
关注