112 Linear and angular momenta of photons in the context of which path experiments of quantum mechanics Masud Mansuripur

2025-04-28 0 0 406.42KB 12 页 10玖币
侵权投诉
1/12
Linear and angular momenta of photons in the context of “which path
experiments of quantum mechanics
Masud Mansuripur
James C. Wyant College of Optical Sciences, The University of Arizona, Tucson
[Published in the Proceedings of SPIE 12198, Optical Trapping and Optical
Micromanipulation XIX, 1219807 (3 October 2022); doi: 10.1117/12.2632866]
Abstract. In optical experiments involving a single photon that takes alternative paths through an
optical system and ultimately interferes with itself (e.g., Young’s double-slit experiment, Mach-
Zehnder interferometer, Sagnac interferometer), there exist fundamental connections between the
linear and angular momenta of the photon on the one hand, and the ability of an observer to
determine the photon’s path through the system on the other hand. This paper examines the
arguments that relate the photon momenta (through the Heisenberg uncertainty principle) to the
“which path” (German: welcher Weg) question at the heart of quantum mechanics. We show that
the linear momenta imparted to apertures or mirrors, or the angular momenta picked up by
strategically placed wave-plates in a system, could lead to an identification of the photon’s path
only at the expense of destroying the corresponding interference effects. We also describe a
thought experiment involving the scattering of a circularly-polarized photon from a pair of small
particles kept at a fixed distance from one another. The exchange of angular momentum between
the photon and the scattering particle in this instance appears to provide the “which path”
information that must, of necessity, wipe out the corresponding interference fringes, although the
fringe-wipe-out mechanism does not seem to involve the uncertainty principle in any obvious way.
1. Introduction. In the historic Bohr-Einstein debates concerning the foundations of quantum
mechanics,1 the Young double-slit experiment of classical optics played a central role. In a nutshell,
Einstein argued that the passage of a single photon could be attributed to one slit or the other, since
the mechanical momentum picked up by the plate housing the slits contains the information needed
to identify the path taken by the photon through the system. Bohr’s counter argument was that
acquiring the “which path” information by way of monitoring the plate’s momentum would, in
accordance with Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle, perturb the position of the plate, thus wiping
out the expected interference fringes.2 In other words, acquisition of the “which path” information,
while revealing the particle-like nature of the photon, would blur the anticipated interference fringes
to the extent that all evidence for the photon’s wave-like behavior will be lost.
The goal of the present paper is to examine a few variations on the theme of the Bohr-Einstein
argument, and to explore the extent to which Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle needs to be relied
upon in the context of “which path” experiments. Feynman has emphasized that, in the absence of
“which path” information, it is the (complex) probability amplitudes of an event that must be added
together, whereas the existence of such information, even in principle, compels one to explain the
outcome of an experiment by directly adding the probabilities associated with individual paths that
could have led to a specific event.3 Thus, wave-like behavior is exhibited when the probability
amplitudes are required to be added together, whereas particle-like behavior emerges in situations
where the probability of occurrence of a multi-path event turns out to be the sum of the probabilities
of its individual paths. We will see in the next section how the availability of “which path”
information (in the form of a photon’s polarization state in the double-slit experiment) wipes out the
interference fringes, and also how the “erasure” of this information causes the fringes to reappear.
A photon of frequency propagating in a given direction in free space, say, along the -axis, is
a wavepacket of energy  and linear momentum ( 
) in the number state |1; here is the
2/12
reduced Planck constant and is the speed of light in vacuum.4 In addition, a circularly-polarized
photon carries angular momentum in the amount of ±, with the plus or minus sign depending on
the sense (or helicity) of its circular polarization. While deflection of a photon’s trajectory at a slit,
or its reflection from a conventional mirror, involves an exchange of linear momentum, its passage
through a birefringent plate could entail an exchange of angular momentum as well.5 We will
discuss examples of systems where the angular momentum transferred to a wave-plate or to a
scatterer can be relied upon to provide the desired “which path” information.
The organization of the paper is as follows. In Sec.2, we examine the canonical Young’s
double-slit experiment6,7 in the special case when a single photon passes through the pair of slits
and interferes with itself at the observation plane. Reconstructing Bohr’s argument in his debates
with Einstein, we show how a straightforward application of Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle
confirms the incompatibility of observing wave-like behavior by the photon (i.e., appearance of
interference fringes) with particle-like behavior (namely, acquisition of information about the slit
through which the photon has passed).1 We proceed to extend the analysis to cases where a phase-
shifter is placed in one of the slits, or when a birefringent window is placed in a slit, to shed
additional light on the nature of Bohr’s complementarity principle.
Section 3 is devoted to an analysis of a single photon passing through a Mach-Zehnder
interferometer,6,7 where the probability amplitudes associated with its passage through one arm or
the other of the device combine to reveal the possibility of observing the effects of interference at
the output ports of the interferometer. It will be seen once again that the acquisition of “which path”
information (by monitoring the mechanical momenta picked up by the mirrors within the device)
disturbs the optical path lengths just enough to eliminate the possibility of observing the anticipated
interference. An alternative method of acquiring the “which path” information (based on placing a
quarter-wave plate in each arm of the interferometer, then monitoring their angular momenta before
and after the passage of the photon) will be shown to similarly ruin the observability of interference.
In the case of the Sagnac interferometer8-10 examined in Sec.4, the mechanical momenta
imparted to the mirrors by a passing photon (or any angular momentum picked up by the device as a
whole) do not contain the desired “which path” information. However, a pair of properly oriented
and strategically placed quarter-wave plates (QWPs) in the system can, in principle, pick up angular
momenta in the amount of ± from their interaction with the passing photon. Once again,
application of the uncertainty principle reveals the impossibility of acquiring “which path”
information without disturbing the necessary conditions for observing the interference effects
associated with the photon’s wave-like behavior.
In Sec.5, we describe a thought experiment involving a right-circularly-polarized (RCP) photon
being scattered from a pair of small particles that are kept at a fixed distance from each other. The
existence of a nonzero probability for the scattered photon to become left-circularly-polarized
(LCP) indicates that the difference  between the angular momenta of the incident and scattered
photons must be picked up by one of the two scatterers. The availability of the “which path”
information in this instance does not appear to disturb the state of the scattered photon in ways that
would prohibit the formation of interference fringes at the observation plane. While invoking the
Heisenberg uncertainty principle in this case does not bring about the disturbances needed to
prevent fringe formation, the entanglement of the state of the pair of particles with that of the
scattered photon guarantees that interference will not occur and that, therefore, the core principle of
wave-particle duality at the heart of quantum mechanics remains inviolate.
The paper closes in Sec.6 with a summary and a few concluding remarks. An Appendix
provides a concise derivation of the Heisenberg uncertainty relation between a pair of non-
commuting observables.
3/12
2. Young’s double-slit experiment. Figure 1 shows a slight variation on the Young double-slit
arrangement,6,7 where the incident light is a single-photon wavepacket in the number state |1,
having frequency , -vector =( 
), and linear polarization
=
. (In terms of the vacuum
wavelength , the magnitude of may be written as = 2 
.) The slits of width are carved
into two separate plates, which are symmetrically positioned in the -plane such that the center-to-
center distance between the slits along the -axis is . The splitting into two separate parts of the
plate that houses the slits is intended to simplify the forthcoming analysis of momentum transfer
from the photon to the plates for purposes of identifying the slit through which the photon has
passed. Let the -field amplitude of the light transmitted through the pair of slits be written as
(,= 0)=rect( 
)[(+ ½)+( ½)], (1)
where () is Dirac’s delta-function, and the standard function rect() equals 1.0 when ||< ½,
zero when ||> ½, and ½ when ||= ½; the asterisk represents the convolution operation, and
the Fourier transform of rect() is rect()d
 = sin() ()=sinc(). Thus, the
Fourier transform of the emergent -field amplitude immediately after the slits is given by
()=()d
 = 2 sinc()cos(). (2)
The product  of the incident wavelength and the Fourier variable appearing in Eq.(2)
represents sin for an emergent plane-wave (corresponding to a geometric-optical ray) at an angle
relative to the -axis; see Fig.1. Thus, in the observation plane in the far field, the ±1st peaks of
the fringe pattern appear at sin = ±  
. To ensure that these fringes do not get blurry (or washed
out), the positions of the two plates that house the slits must each have an uncertainty along the
-axis much less than , say,  = with 0.1. The visibility of the fringes that are further
away from the center of the observation plane requires progressively smaller values of .
A photon arriving at the center of a first bright fringe on one side or the other of the central
fringe will have the following -component of momentum:
( 
)sin = ±(2 
)( 
)= ±2 
. (3)
Fig.1. A slight variation on Young’s double-slit experiment, where the plate containing the slits (width
=, separation =) is split in the middle, so that, in the wake of a single photon’s passage through
either slit, the -component of momentum transferred to the corresponding half-plate can be monitored.
x
z
d
L
θ
摘要:

1/12Linearandangularmomentaofphotonsinthecontextof“whichpath”experimentsofquantummechanicsMasudMansuripurJamesC.WyantCollegeofOpticalSciences,TheUniversityofArizona,Tucson[PublishedintheProceedingsofSPIE12198,OpticalTrappingandOpticalMicromanipulationXIX,1219807(3October2022);doi:10.1117/12.2632866]...

展开>> 收起<<
112 Linear and angular momenta of photons in the context of which path experiments of quantum mechanics Masud Mansuripur.pdf

共12页,预览3页

还剩页未读, 继续阅读

声明:本站为文档C2C交易模式,即用户上传的文档直接被用户下载,本站只是中间服务平台,本站所有文档下载所得的收益归上传人(含作者)所有。玖贝云文库仅提供信息存储空间,仅对用户上传内容的表现方式做保护处理,对上载内容本身不做任何修改或编辑。若文档所含内容侵犯了您的版权或隐私,请立即通知玖贝云文库,我们立即给予删除!
分类:图书资源 价格:10玖币 属性:12 页 大小:406.42KB 格式:PDF 时间:2025-04-28

开通VIP享超值会员特权

  • 多端同步记录
  • 高速下载文档
  • 免费文档工具
  • 分享文档赚钱
  • 每日登录抽奖
  • 优质衍生服务
/ 12
客服
关注