(E-Books) Stephen Hawking - The Nature Of Space And Time

VIP免费
2024-12-14 0 0 364.31KB 61 页 5.9玖币
侵权投诉
hep-th/9409195 30 Sep 94
1. Classical Theory
S. W. Hawking
In these lectures Roger Penrose and I will put forward our related but rather different
viewpoints on the nature of space and time. We shall speak alternately and shall give three
lectures each, followed by a discussion on our different approaches. I should emphasize that
these will be technical lectures. We shall assume a basic knowledge of general relativity
and quantum theory.
There is a short article by Richard Feynman describing his experiences at a conference
on general relativity. I think it was the Warsaw conference in 1962. It commented very
unfavorably on the general competence of the people there and the relevance of what
they were doing. That general relativity soon acquired a much better reputation, and
more interest, is in a considerable measure because of Roger’s work. Up to then, general
relativity had been formulated as a messy set of partial differential equations in a single
coordinate system. People were so pleased when they found a solution that they didn’t
care that it probably had no physical significance. However, Roger brought in modern
concepts like spinors and global methods. He was the first to show that one could discover
general properties without solving the equations exactly. It was his first singularity theorem
that introduced me to the study of causal structure and inspired my classical work on
singularities and black holes.
I think Roger and I pretty much agree on the classical work. However, we differ in
our approach to quantum gravity and indeed to quantum theory itself. Although I’m
regarded as a dangerous radical by particle physicists for proposing that there may be loss
of quantum coherence I’m definitely a conservative compared to Roger. I take the positivist
viewpoint that a physical theory is just a mathematical model and that it is meaningless
to ask whether it corresponds to reality. All that one can ask is that its predictions should
be in agreement with observation. I think Roger is a Platonist at heart but he must answer
for himself.
Although there have been suggestions that spacetime may have a discrete structure
I see no reason to abandon the continuum theories that have been so successful. General
relativity is a beautiful theory that agrees with every observation that has been made. It
may require modifications on the Planck scale but I don’t think that will affect many of
the predictions that can be obtained from it. It may be only a low energy approximation
to some more fundemental theory, like string theory, but I think string theory has been
over sold. First of all, it is not clear that general relativity, when combined with various
other fields in a supergravity theory, can not give a sensible quantum theory. Reports of
1
the death of supergravity are exaggerations. One year everyone believed that supergravity
was finite. The next year the fashion changed and everyone said that supergravity was
bound to have divergences even though none had actually been found. My second reason
for not discussing string theory is that it has not made any testable predictions. By
contrast, the straight forward application of quantum theory to general relativity, which I
will be talking about, has already made two testable predictions. One of these predictions,
the development of small perturbations during inflation, seems to be confirmed by recent
observations of fluctuations in the microwave background. The other prediction, that
black holes should radiate thermally, is testable in principle. All we have to do is find a
primordial black hole. Unfortunately, there don’t seem many around in this neck of the
woods. If there had been we would know how to quantize gravity.
Neither of these predictions will be changed even if string theory is the ultimate
theory of nature. But string theory, at least at its current state of development, is quite
incapable of making these predictions except by appealing to general relativity as the low
energy effective theory. I suspect this may always be the case and that there may not be
any observable predictions of string theory that can not also be predicted from general
relativity or supergravity. If this is true it raises the question of whether string theory is a
genuine scientific theory. Is mathematical beauty and completeness enough in the absence
of distinctive observationally tested predictions. Not that string theory in its present form
is either beautiful or complete.
For these reasons, I shall talk about general relativity in these lectures. I shall con-
centrate on two areas where gravity seems to lead to features that are completely different
from other field theories. The first is the idea that gravity should cause spacetime to have
a begining and maybe an end. The second is the discovery that there seems to be intrinsic
gravitational entropy that is not the result of coarse graining. Some people have claimed
that these predictions are just artifacts of the semi classical approximation. They say that
string theory, the true quantum theory of gravity, will smear out the singularities and will
introduce correlations in the radiation from black holes so that it is only approximately
thermal in the coarse grained sense. It would be rather boring if this were the case. Grav-
ity would be just like any other field. But I believe it is distinctively different, because
it shapes the arena in which it acts, unlike other fields which act in a fixed spacetime
background. It is this that leads to the possibility of time having a begining. It also leads
to regions of the universe which one can’t observe, which in turn gives rise to the concept
of gravitational entropy as a measure of what we can’t know.
In this lecture I shall review the work in classical general relativity that leads to these
ideas. In the second and third lectures I shall show how they are changed and extended
2
when one goes to quantum theory. Lecture two will be about black holes and lecture three
will be on quantum cosmology.
The crucial technique for investigating singularities and black holes that was intro-
duced by Roger, and which I helped develop, was the study of the global causal structure
of spacetime.
Time
Space
Null geodesics through p
generating part of
Null geodesic in (p) which
does not go back to p and has
no past end point
Point removed
from spacetime
Chronological
future
p+
.
I(p)
+
I(p) +
.
I
Define I+(p) to be the set of all points of the spacetime Mthat can be reached from pby
future directed time like curves. One can think of I+(p) as the set of all events that can
be influenced by what happens at p. There are similar definitions in which plus is replaced
by minus and future by past. I shall regard such definitions as self evident.
q
p
+
.
I(S)
.
timelike curve
+
I(S)
+
I(S) can't be timelike
q
+
.
I(S)
.
+
I(S)
+
I(S) can't be spacelike
All timelike curves from q leave +
I(S)
One now considers the boundary ˙
I+(S)ofthefutureofasetS. It is fairly easy to
see that this boundary can not be time like. For in that case, a point qjust outside the
boundary would be to the future of a point pjust inside. Nor can the boundary of the
3
future be space like, except at the set Sitself. For in that case every past directed curve
from a point q, just to the future of the boundary, would cross the boundary and leave the
future of S. That would be a contradiction with the fact that qis in the future of S.
q
+
.
I(S)
null geodesic segment in
+
I(S)
q
+
I(S)
+
.
I(S)
null geodesic segment in
+
.
I(S)
future end point of generators of
One therefore concludes that the boundary of the future is null apart from at Sitself.
More precisely, if qis in the boundary of the future but is not in the closure of Sthere
is a past directed null geodesic segment through qlying in the boundary. There may be
more than one null geodesic segment through qlying in the boundary, but in that case q
will be a future end point of the segments. In other words, the boundary of the future of
Sis generated by null geodesics that have a future end point in the boundary and pass
into the interior of the future if they intersect another generator. On the other hand, the
null geodesic generators can have past end points only on S. It is possible, however, to
have spacetimes in which there are generators of the boundary of the future of a set Sthat
never intersect S. Such generators can have no past end point.
A simple example of this is Minkowski space with a horizontal line segment removed.
If the set Slies to the past of the horizontal line, the line will cast a shadow and there
will be points just to the future of the line that are not in the future of S. There will be
a generator of the boundary of the future of Sthat goes back to the end of the horizontal
4
+
.
I
+
I(S)
S
line removed from
Minkowski space
generator of (S)
with no end point on S
+
.
I
generators of (S)
with past end point on S
line. However, as the end point of the horizontal line has been removed from spacetime,
this generator of the boundary will have no past end point. This spacetime is incomplete,
but one can cure this by multiplying the metric by a suitable conformal factor near the
end of the horizontal line. Although spaces like this are very artificial they are important
in showing how careful you have to be in the study of causal structure. In fact Roger
Penrose, who was one of my PhD examiners, pointed out that a space like that I have just
described was a counter example to some of the claims I made in my thesis.
To show that each generator of the boundary of the future has a past end point on
the set one has to impose some global condition on the causal structure. The strongest
and physically most important condition is that of global hyperbolicity.
q
p
+
I(p) _
I(q)
An open set Uis said to be globally hyperbolic if:
1) for every pair of points pand qin Uthe intersection of the future of pand the past
of qhas compact closure. In other words, it is a bounded diamond shaped region.
2) strong causality holds on U. That is there are no closed or almost closed time like
curves contained in U.
5
p
every timelike curve
intersects (t)
(t)
Σ
Σ
The physical significance of global hyperbolicity comes from the fact that it implies
that there is a family of Cauchy surfaces Σ(t)forU. A Cauchy surface for Uis a space
like or null surface that intersects every time like curve in Uonce and once only. One can
predict what will happen in Ufrom data on the Cauchy surface, and one can formulate a
well behaved quantum field theory on a globally hyperbolic background. Whether one can
formulate a sensible quantum field theory on a non globally hyperbolic background is less
clear. So global hyperbolicity may be a physical necessity. But my view point is that one
shouldn’t assume it because that may be ruling out something that gravity is trying to
tell us. Rather one should deduce that certain regions of spacetime are globally hyperbolic
from other physically reasonable assumptions.
The significance of global hyperbolicity for singularity theorems stems from the fol-
lowing.
q
p
geodesic of
maximum length
6
Let Ube globally hyperbolic and let pand qbe points of Uthat can be joined by a
time like or null curve. Then there is a time like or null geodesic between pand qwhich
maximizes the length of time like or null curves from pto q. The method of proof is to
show the space of all time like or null curves from pto qis compact in a certain topology.
One then shows that the length of the curve is an upper semi continuous function on this
space. It must therefore attain its maximum and the curve of maximum length will be a
geodesic because otherwise a small variation will give a longer curve.
q
r
p
geodesic
point conjugate
to p along neighbouring
geodesic
γ
γ
p
q
r
non-minimal
geodesic minimal geodesic
without conjugate points
point conjugate to p
One can now consider the second variation of the length of a geodesic γ. One can show
that γcan be varied to a longer curve if there is an infinitesimally neighbouring geodesic
from pwhich intersects γagain at a point rbetween pand q.Thepointris said to be
conjugate to p. One can illustrate this by considering two points pand qon the surface of
the Earth. Without loss of generality one can take pto be at the north pole. Because the
Earth has a positive definite metric rather than a Lorentzian one, there is a geodesic of
minimal length, rather than a geodesic of maximum length. This minimal geodesic will be
a line of longtitude running from the north pole to the point q. But there will be another
geodesic from pto qwhich runs down the back from the north pole to the south pole and
then up to q. This geodesic contains a point conjugate to pat the south pole where all the
geodesics from pintersect. Both geodesics from pto qare stationary points of the length
under a small variation. But now in a positive definite metric the second variation of a
geodesic containing a conjugate point can give a shorter curve from pto q.Thus,inthe
example of the Earth, we can deduce that the geodesic that goes down to the south pole
and then comes up is not the shortest curve from pto q. This example is very obvious.
However, in the case of spacetime one can show that under certain assumptions there
7
ought to be a globally hyperbolic region in which there ought to be conjugate points on
every geodesic between two points. This establishes a contradiction which shows that the
assumption of geodesic completeness, which can be taken as a definition of a non singular
spacetime, is false.
The reason one gets conjugate points in spacetime is that gravity is an attractive force.
It therefore curves spacetime in such a way that neighbouring geodesics are bent towards
each other rather than away. One can see this from the Raychaudhuri or Newman-Penrose
equation, which I will write in a unified form.
Raychaudhuri - Newman - Penrose equation
dv =ρ2+σij σij +1
nRablalb
where n= 2 for null geodesics
n= 3 for timelike geodesics
Here vis an affine parameter along a congruence of geodesics, with tangent vector la
which are hypersurface orthogonal. The quantity ρis the average rate of convergence of
the geodesics, while σmeasures the shear. The term Rablalbgives the direct gravitational
effect of the matter on the convergence of the geodesics.
Einstein equation
Rab 1
2gabR=8πTab
Weak Energy Condition
Tabvavb0
for any timelike vector va.
By the Einstein equations, it will be non negative for any null vector laif the matter obeys
the so called weak energy condition. This says that the energy density T00 is non negative
in any frame. The weak energy condition is obeyed by the classical energy momentum
tensor of any reasonable matter, such as a scalar or electro magnetic field or a fluid with
8
a reasonable equation of state. It may not however be satisfied locally by the quantum
mechanical expectation value of the energy momentum tensor. This will be relevant in my
second and third lectures.
Suppose the weak energy condition holds, and that the null geodesics from a point p
begin to converge again and that ρhas the positive value ρ0. Then the Newman Penrose
equation would imply that the convergence ρwould become infinite at a point qwithin an
affine parameter distance 1
ρ0if the null geodesic can be extended that far.
If ρ=ρ0at v=v0then ρ1
ρ1+v0v. Thus there is a conjugate point
before v=v0+ρ1.
q
pneighbouring geodesics
meeting at q
future end point
of in (p)
crossing region
of light cone
inside (p)
+
I
γ
γ+
I
Infinitesimally neighbouring null geodesics from pwill intersect at q. This means the point
qwill be conjugate to palong the null geodesic γjoining them. For points on γbeyond
the conjugate point qthere will be a variation of γthat gives a time like curve from p.
Thus γcan not lie in the boundary of the future of pbeyond the conjugate point q.Soγ
will have a future end point as a generator of the boundary of the future of p.
The situation with time like geodesics is similar, except that the strong energy con-
dition that is required to make Rablalbnon negative for every time like vector lais, as
its name suggests, rather stronger. It is still however physically reasonable, at least in an
averaged sense, in classical theory. If the strong energy condition holds, and the time like
geodesics from pbegin converging again, then there will be a point qconjugate to p.
Finally there is the generic energy condition. This says that first the strong energy
condition holds. Second, every time like or null geodesic encounters some point where
9
Strong Energy Condition
Tabvavb1
2vavaT
there is some curvature that is not specially aligned with the geodesic. The generic energy
condition is not satisfied by a number of known exact solutions. But these are rather
special. One would expect it to be satisfied by a solution that was ”generic” in an appro-
priate sense. If the generic energy condition holds, each geodesic will encounter a region
of gravitational focussing. This will imply that there are pairs of conjugate points if one
can extend the geodesic far enough in each direction.
The Generic Energy Condition
1. The strong energy condition holds.
2. Every timelike or null geodesic contains a point where l[aRb]cd[elf]lcld6=0.
One normally thinks of a spacetime singularity as a region in which the curvature
becomes unboundedly large. However, the trouble with that as a definition is that one
could simply leave out the singular points and say that the remaining manifold was the
whole of spacetime. It is therefore better to define spacetime as the maximal manifold on
which the metric is suitably smooth. One can then recognize the occurrence of singularities
by the existence of incomplete geodesics that can not be extended to infinite values of the
affine parameter.
Definition of Singularity
A spacetime is singular if it is timelike or null geodesically incomplete, but
can not be embedded in a larger spacetime.
This definition reflects the most objectionable feature of singularities, that there can be
particles whose history has a begining or end at a finite time. There are examples in which
geodesic incompleteness can occur with the curvature remaining bounded, but it is thought
that generically the curvature will diverge along incomplete geodesics. This is important if
one is to appeal to quantum effects to solve the problems raised by singularities in classical
general relativity.
10
摘要:

hep-th/940919530Sep941.ClassicalTheoryS.W.HawkingIntheselecturesRogerPenroseandIwillputforwardourrelatedbutratherdi erentviewpointsonthenatureofspaceandtime.Weshallspeakalternatelyandshallgivethreelectureseach,followedbyadiscussiononourdi erentapproaches.Ishouldemphasizethatthesewillbetechnicallectu...

展开>> 收起<<
(E-Books) Stephen Hawking - The Nature Of Space And Time.pdf

共61页,预览13页

还剩页未读, 继续阅读

声明:本站为文档C2C交易模式,即用户上传的文档直接被用户下载,本站只是中间服务平台,本站所有文档下载所得的收益归上传人(含作者)所有。玖贝云文库仅提供信息存储空间,仅对用户上传内容的表现方式做保护处理,对上载内容本身不做任何修改或编辑。若文档所含内容侵犯了您的版权或隐私,请立即通知玖贝云文库,我们立即给予删除!

相关推荐

分类:外语学习 价格:5.9玖币 属性:61 页 大小:364.31KB 格式:PDF 时间:2024-12-14

开通VIP享超值会员特权

  • 多端同步记录
  • 高速下载文档
  • 免费文档工具
  • 分享文档赚钱
  • 每日登录抽奖
  • 优质衍生服务
/ 61
客服
关注