Admissible Causal Structures and Correlations Eleftherios-Ermis Tselentis1 2and Amin Baumeler3 4 1Institute for Quantum Optics and Quantum Information IQOQI-Vienna

2025-05-06 0 0 603.42KB 11 页 10玖币
侵权投诉
Admissible Causal Structures and Correlations
Eleftherios-Ermis Tselentis
1, 2
and
¨
Amin Baumeler
3, 4
1
Institute for Quantum Optics and Quantum Information (IQOQI-Vienna),
Austrian Academy of Sciences, 1090 Vienna, Austria
2
Faculty of Physics, University of Vienna, 1090 Vienna, Austria
3
Facolt`a di scienze informatiche, Universit`a della Svizzera italiana, 6900 Lugano, Switzerland
4
Facolt`a indipendente di Gandria, 6978 Gandria, Switzerland
It is well-known that if one assumes quantum theory to hold locally, then processes with indefinite
causal order and cyclic causal structures become feasible. Here, we study qualitative limitations on
causal structures and correlations imposed by local quantum theory. For one, we find a necessary
graph-theoretic criterion—the “siblings-on-cycles” property—for a causal structure to be admissible:
Only such causal structures admit a realization consistent with local quantum theory. We conjecture
that this property is moreover sufficient. This conjecture is motivated by an explicit construction of
quantum causal models, and supported by numerical calculations. We show that these causal models,
in a restricted setting, are indeed consistent. For another, we identify two sets of causal structures
that, in the classical-deterministic case, forbid and give rise to non-causal correlations respectively.
INTRODUCTION
At heart of Einstein’s equivalence principle is the im-
possibility to detect the gravitational field via local ex-
periments.
1
For general relativity, this principle dictates
that physics in sufficiently small, i.e., local, space-time
regions is described by special relativity. This princi-
ple naturally extends to the quantum case: local experi-
ments are described by quantum theory. In this quantum
formulation, however, the gravitational field, the refer-
ence frames, and the space-time regions might necessitate
quantum descriptions. While different approaches target
these descriptions (see, e.g., Refs. [
2
5
]), another—the
process-matrix framework [
6
]—abstracts away the general-
relativistic freight and focuses on the idealized prescription
of local quantum experiments in countably many regions
only (without imposing any global constraints). Similar
to the various formulations of the equivalence principles,
this approach can be used to constrain competing theories
of quantum gravity: If a candidate theory of quantum
gravity exceeds the limits of the latter, then local experi-
ments in that theory must disagree with quantum theory.
This, in turn, gives a prescription to experimentally falsify
that candidate theory.
The process-matrix framework, i.e., the assumption
of local quantum theory, reconciles the inherently prob-
abilistic nature of quantum theory with the dynamical
causal structures of general relativity [
7
]. For one, it
extends quantum indefiniteness of physical degrees of
freedom like position and momentum to causal connec-
tions. Exemplary, while the position of a mass in general
1
This means that if a non-gravitational experiment is carried out
in a sufficiently small space-time region
R
with a gravitational
field, then for any space-time region
R
free of gravitation there
exists a suitable reference frame where the same experimental
procedure yields the identical experimental data. This statement
and its variations are discussed in Ref. [1].
relativity determines the causal order among events in
its future, the quantum-switch process [
8
] does so co-
herently [
9
11
]. For another, this framework allows for
violations of causal inequalities [
6
]. Causal inequalities,
similar to Bell inequalities [
12
], are device-independent
tests of a global causal order. If the observed correlations
violate such an inequality, then they cannot be causally ex-
plained: Any explanation where only past data influences
future observations fails. These correlations are called
non-causal, and arise in setups that resemble [
13
] closed
time-like curves (CTCs) [
14
,
15
]. As notoriously shown
by G¨odel [
15
], CTCs appear in solutions to Einstein’s
equation of general relativity.
This stipulation of local quantum theory is also of
interest in theoretical computer science. A pillar of com-
puter sciences is that machines (programs) and data are
treated on an equal footing. This paradigm finds its
climax in Church’s notion of computation—the
λ
calcu-
lus [
16
]—where any data is a function, and therefore
functions are of higher-order: functions on functions.
The process-matrix framework describes the first level of
higher-order quantum computation [
17
,
18
]: Its objects—
the process matrices—map quantum gates to quantum
gates. For instance, the previously mentioned quantum
switch maps two quantum gates
A, B
to the functional-
ity
(α|0+β|1)⊗ |ψ⟩ 7→ α|0⟩ ⊗ BA|ψ+β|1⟩ ⊗ AB|ψ
where the order of gate application is controlled by
the first qubit. This is achieved, e.g., through pro-
grammable connections between gates [
19
]. The quan-
tum switch brings forth a reduction in query complexity
when compared to the standard circuit model of compu-
tation [8,2022].
The causal relations among local quantum experi-
ments (gates) are conveniently expressed with causal
structures. A causal structure is a directed graph where
the vertices represent laboratories, and where the edges
indicate the possibility of a local laboratory to directly
influence another (see Figure 1). The causal relations
arXiv:2210.12796v2 [quant-ph] 16 Sep 2023
2
A
BCD
E
F
A
B
C
D
E
F
(a)
PA
B
F
P
A
B
F
(b)
A
P F
A
P F
(c)
Figure 1: (a) A quantum circuit and its acyclic causal
structure. (b) The quantum switch—an instance of the
process-matrix framework—has a cyclic causal structure:
Depending on the prepared state at P, a quantum
system is sent through the H-shaped region from
A
to
B
or from Bto A. (c) If Ais traversed by a closed
time-like curve, then
A
’s output influences the input, and
a departure from quantum theory becomes necessary.
among the gates of any quantum circuit form an acyclic
causal structure: Naturally, a gate at depth
d
of the circuit
has no causal influence on the input to any other gate at
the same or smaller depth. This is radically contrasted by
processes: The quantum switch, for instance, has a cyclic
causal structure [
23
]. Still, not every causal structure is
compatible with local quantum theory: For the output of
a laboratory to influence the same laboratory’s input, we
require a departure from quantum theory by introducing
non-linear dynamics [2426].
In this work, we study the causal structures that admit
a quantum realization—a question raised in Ref. [
27
].
In other words: We study the possible causal relations
among laboratories under the assumptions that within
each laboratory no deviation from quantum theory is
observable. We find a necessary graph-theoretic criterion
(the causal structure of every quantum process satisfies
this criterion) and conjecture that the criterion is also
sufficient. The conjecture is motivated by a construction
of causal models for the causal structures of interest,
and is moreover numerically tested for all directed graph
with up to six nodes. In addition, we provide two graph-
theoretic criteria from which, in the classical-deterministic
case, only causal or also non-causal correlations arise.
Supporting the above conjecture, we show that the causal
structures that satisfy the criterion for non-violation are
admissible.
The presentation is structured in the following way.
First, we provide the mathematical tools necessary for
the present treatment. This is followed by our results on
admissible and inadmissible causal structures. Thereafter,
we relate causal structures with causal inequalities. We
conclude with a series of open questions.
PRELIMINARIES
We briefly comment on the notation used. If
H
is
a Hilbert space, then
L
(
H
) is the set of linear operators
on
H
. We use
Zn
for the set
{
0
,
1
, . . . , n
1
}
. If a sym-
bol is used with and without a subscript from
Zn
, then
the bare symbol denotes the collection under the natu-
ral composition, e.g., we will use
x
to denote (
xk
)
kZn
.
If the subscript is a subset of
Zn
, then the composi-
tion is taken only over those elements. Moreover, we
use
\S
as shorthand for
Zn\S
, and
\i
for
\{i}
. If
ε
is a completely positive map, then
ρε
is its Choi oper-
ator [
28
]. For a directed graph
G= (V, E V×V)
,
V
denotes the set of nodes and Ethe set of directed edges.
Adirected path
π= (v0, . . . , v)
is a sequence of distinct
nodes with
{(vi, vi+1)|0i<ℓ} ⊆ E
. A directed cy-
cle
C= (v0, . . . , v)
is a directed path with (
v, v0
)
E
.
The induced graph
G
[
V
] is the graph
G
= (
V, E
)
where
VV
and all edges
EE
have endpoints in
V
,
i.e., (
i, j
)
E
if and only if
i, j V
and (
i, j
)
E
. A di-
rected cycle
C
is called induced directed cycle or chordless
cycle if the induced graph
G
[
C
] is a directed cycle graph.
For a node
kV
, we use
Pa
(
k
),
Ch
(
k
), and
Anc
(
k
) to
express the set of parents, children, and ancestors of
k
,
respectively, and similarly
Pa
(
S
),
Ch
(
S
) and
Anc
(
S
) by
taking the union over a set
S
. The cardinality of the
set
Pa
(
k
) is the in-degree
degin
(
k
). A node with zero
in-degree is called source. We use
CPa
(
S
) for the union
of the common parents of all elements
i̸
=
jS
,i.e.,
CPa
(
S
) :=
Si̸=jSPa
(
i
)
Pa
(
j
). Two nodes
i, j V
are
called siblings if and only if they have common parents,
i.e.,
CPa
(
{i, j}
)
̸
=
. A directed path
π
is said to contain
siblings if and only if CPa(π)̸=.
Correlations
Correlations observed among
n
parties (regions)
Zn
are expressed with the conditional probability distribu-
tion
p
(
a|x
) where for each party
k
we have
ak∈ Ak
,
and
xk∈ Xk
. The set
Xk
is the set of experimental
settings and Akthe set of experimental observations.
Definition 1 (Causal correlations [
6
,
9
,
29
]).The
n
-party
correlations
p
(
a|x
) are causal if and only if they can be
decomposed as
p(a|x) = X
kZn
qkp(ak|xk)pxk
ak(a\k|x\k),(1)
where
kZn
:
qk
0,
PkZnqk
= 1, and
pxk
ak(a\k|x\k)
are (
n
1)-party causal correlations. If this decomposition
is infeasible, the correlations are called non-causal.
The motivation behind this definition is that each party
can influence its future only, including the causal order
of the parties in its future. From this follows that there
3
O0
I0
O1
I1
O2
I2
µa0|x0
0µa1|x1
1µa2|x2
2
Figure 2: Schematic of three parties and a process. The
gray area represents the process: It takes the systems on
the future boundaries of the parties and maps it to the
past boundaries of the parties. The red connections
indicate an example where the parties are causally
ordered increasingly. A priori, however, the process is
not assumed to respect any ordering of the parties.
exists at least one party
k
whose observation does not
depend on the data of any other party (the value of
ak
depends solely on
xk
). Moreover, the causal order among
the parties might be subject to randomness, e.g., a coin
flip.
Processes
In the process-matrix framework [
6
], each party (re-
gion) is defined through a past and future space-like
boundary (see Figure 2). For party
k
, we denote
by
Ik
the Hilbert space on the past, by
Ok
the Hilbert
space on the future boundary, and by
CPk
(
CPTPk
)
the set of all completely positive (trace-preserving)
maps from
L
(
Ik
) to
L
(
Ok
). A quantum experiment
for party
k
is a quantum channel from
Ik
to
Ok
,
equipped with a classical input (the setting) and a clas-
sical output (the observation). Hence, it is a fam-
ily
{µak|xk
kCPk}(ak,xk)∈Ak×Xk
of maps, such that for
all
xk∈ Xk
, we have
Pak∈Akµak|xk
kCPTPk
. A pro-
cess interlinks all parties without any assumption on
their causal relations, but with the sole assumption that
no deviation from quantum theory is locally observable,
i.e., the probability distribution over the observations
is a multi-linear function of the quantum experiments
and well-defined (even if the parties share an arbitrary
quantum system).
Definition 2 (Process [
6
]).An
n
-party quantum process
is a positive semi-definite operator W∈ L(I ⊗ O) with
∀{µkCPTPk}kZn: Tr "WO
kZn
ρµk#= 1 .(2)
Note that in this definition, the experimental set-
tings and observations are absent, or equivalently, the
sets
Ak,Xk
are singletons. Eq.
(2)
states that the total
probability of observing this single outcome under this
single setting is one; this holds for any setting and is inde-
pendent of any resolution of the completely positive trace-
preserving map into maps with classical outputs. Ore-
shkov, Costa, and Brukner [
6
] already observed that the
quantum process
W
is the Choi operator of a completely
positive trace-preserving map from all future boundaries
to all past boundaries of the parties (cf. Figure 2). For
a given choice of
n
-party quantum process and experi-
ments, the correlations are computed with the generalized
Born rule
p(a|x) := Tr "WO
kZn
ρµak|xk
k#.(3)
If one assumes that the parties perform classical-
deterministic experiments, as opposed to quantum experi-
ments, we arrive at the following special case. The spaces
on the past and future boundaries
Ik,Ok
are sets (as op-
posed to Hilbert spaces), and an experiment for party
k
is a function
µk:Ik× Xk→ Ok× Ak
(as opposed to a
family of maps), where we use
µ0
k:Ik× Xk→ Ok
for the
first, and
µ1
k:Ik× Xk→ Ak
for the second component.
Just as in the quantum case, a classical-deterministic
process
ω
turns out to be a function from the future
to the past boundaries, and Eq.
(2)
translates into an
intuitive condition: For any choice of experiment, there
exists a unique consistent assignment of values to the
input spaces; the map ωµhas a unique fixed point.
Theorem 1 (Classical-determintic process [
30
]).
An
n
-party classical-deterministic process is a func-
tion ω:O → I with
∀{µk:Ik→ Ok}kZn,!(rk)kZn:r=ω(µ(r)) ,(4)
where !is the uniqueness quantifier.
Here, the correlations among the
n
-parties are com-
puted via
p(a|x) := ω ⋆ µa|x=X
i,o
[ω(o) = i] [(o, a) = µ(x, i)] ,(5)
where we use [
n
=
m
] for the Kronecker delta
δn,m
, and
for the link product [
31
]. Note that every
n
-party classical-
deterministic process
ω
also corresponds to an
n
-party
quantum process [27]
Wω:= X
o∈O
|o⟩⟨o|O⊗ |ω(o)⟩⟨ω(o)|I,(6)
where
|o
=
NkZn|ok
, with
{|o
k⟩}o
k∈Ok
being a basis
for all kZn, and similarly for |ω(o).
We briefly illustrate the above theorem in the single-
party case (
n
= 1). Assume the function
ω
is the iden-
tity function from
O
=
{
0
,
1
}
to
I
=
{
0
,
1
}
. Here,
ω
describes a closed time-like curve: The output of that
single party is identically mapped to the same party’s
摘要:

AdmissibleCausalStructuresandCorrelationsEleftherios-ErmisTselentis1,2and¨AminBaumeler3,41InstituteforQuantumOpticsandQuantumInformation(IQOQI-Vienna),AustrianAcademyofSciences,1090Vienna,Austria2FacultyofPhysics,UniversityofVienna,1090Vienna,Austria3Facolt`adiscienzeinformatiche,Universit`adellaSvi...

展开>> 收起<<
Admissible Causal Structures and Correlations Eleftherios-Ermis Tselentis1 2and Amin Baumeler3 4 1Institute for Quantum Optics and Quantum Information IQOQI-Vienna.pdf

共11页,预览3页

还剩页未读, 继续阅读

声明:本站为文档C2C交易模式,即用户上传的文档直接被用户下载,本站只是中间服务平台,本站所有文档下载所得的收益归上传人(含作者)所有。玖贝云文库仅提供信息存储空间,仅对用户上传内容的表现方式做保护处理,对上载内容本身不做任何修改或编辑。若文档所含内容侵犯了您的版权或隐私,请立即通知玖贝云文库,我们立即给予删除!
分类:图书资源 价格:10玖币 属性:11 页 大小:603.42KB 格式:PDF 时间:2025-05-06

开通VIP享超值会员特权

  • 多端同步记录
  • 高速下载文档
  • 免费文档工具
  • 分享文档赚钱
  • 每日登录抽奖
  • 优质衍生服务
/ 11
客服
关注