
a channel and a prior. Second, we see no reason to assume that the time-reversal assignment
must be linear in either the channel or the prior, as is done in [25,27] (see axiom 4 on page 2
in [27] or the definition of symmetry in [25]). Indeed, even classical Bayesian inversion is linear in
neither the original process nor the prior, so there is no reason to assume linearity in the quantum
setting, which should specialize to the classical theory. In fact, in the present work, we axiomatize
retrodiction in a way that is agnostic to classical or quantum theory, probability theory, and even
any physical theory as long as it has sufficient structure to describe states and evolution. This is
achieved by formulating a rigorous definition of retrodiction in the language of category theory,
the proper mathematical language for describing processes [43,44,45,46,47,28].
Fortunately, it is possible to summarize our axioms intuitively without requiring familiarity
with category theory.1In order to be agnostic to classical or quantum theory, we try to avoid
using language that is only applicable to either. To describe retrodiction, we should first specify
the collection of allowed systems (denoted A,B,C, . . . ), processes (denoted E,F, . . . ), and states
(denoted α, β, γ, . . . ). Having done this, and as argued above, in order to define the retrodiction of
some process E:A→Bfrom one system Ato another B, it is necessary to have some additional
input. For us, that input is a prior α, which is a state on system A. Hence, we will combine these
data together by writing (α, E). Retrodiction should be some assignment whose input is such a
pair (α, E)and whose output is some map Rα,E:B→Athat only depends on this input (this is
sometimes called universality in the literature).
The definition of retrodiction that we propose consists of the following logical axioms on such
an assignment Rover all systems A,B,C, . . . , evolutions (i.e., processes) E,F, . . . , and states
α, β, γ, . . . (remarks and clarifications on these axioms follow immediately after).
1. Retrodiction should produce valid processes, i.e., the map Rα,Eshould be a valid process.
2. The map Rα,Eshould take the prediction E(α)back to the prior α, i.e., Rα,E(E(α)) = α.
3. The retrodiction of the process that does nothing is also the process that does nothing, i.e.,
Rα,idA= idA.
4. More generally, the retrodiction of a genuinely reversible process E:A→Bis the inverse
E−1of the original process, i.e., Rα,E=E−1, and is therefore independent of the prior.
5. Retrodiction is involutive in the sense that retrodicting on a retrodiction gives back the
original process, i.e., RE(α),Rα,E=E.
6. Retrodiction is compositional in the sense that if one has a prior αon system Aand two
successive processes E:A→Band F:B→C, then the retrodiction Rα,F◦E associated with
the composite process AE
−→ BF
−→ Cis the composite of the retrodictions RE(α),F:C→Band
Rα,E:B→Aassociated with the constituent components, i.e., Rα,F◦E =Rα,E◦RE(α),F.
7. Retrodiction is tensorial in the sense that if one has priors αand α0on systems Aand A0,
respectively, as well as two processes E:A→Band E0:A0→B0, then the retrodiction
Rα⊗α0,E⊗E0:B⊗B0→A⊗A0associated with the tensor product of the systems and
processes is equal to the tensor product Rα,E⊗Rα0,E0of the constituent retrodictions, i.e.,
Rα⊗α0,E⊗E0=Rα,E⊗Rα0,E0.
Several clarifications and remarks are in order with regard to these axioms, which we enumerate
in the same order.
1. Part of our axioms assume that we have identified a class of physical systems and processes.
In the setting of quantum theory, and in this work, physical systems A,B,C, . . . will be
mathematically represented by their corresponding algebras, following the conventions of
1In the body of this work, only elementary ideas from category theory will be used to formalize our definitions
and results. If the reader is comfortable with the definitions of a monoidal category, its opposite, and functor, this
should suffice. We will try to ease into this through our setting of retrodiction rather than giving formal definitions.
The reader is encouraged to read [48] for a first impression of category theory and then browse the reference [49,
Chapter 1] for a more detailed, yet friendly, introduction. References that cover advanced topics while maintaining
a close connection to quantum physics include [50,44,51]. Finally, standard in-depth references include [52,53].
Accepted in Quantum 2023-04-10, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 3