1/21
Spin-1 photons, spin-½ electrons, Bell’s inequalities, and Feynman’s
special perspective on quantum mechanics
Masud Mansuripur
James C. Wyant College of Optical Sciences, The University of Arizona, Tucson
[Published in Proceedings of SPIE 12205, Spintronics XV, 122050B (3 October 2022); doi: 10.1117/12.2633646]
Abstract. The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen (EPR) paradox that argues for the incompleteness of quantum
mechanics as a description of physical reality has been put to rest by John Bell’s famous theorem,
which inspired numerous experimental tests and brought about further affirmations of quantum reality.
Nevertheless, in his writings and public presentations, Richard Feynman never acknowledged the
significance of Bell’s contribution to the resolution of the EPR paradox. In this paper, we discuss
several variants of the Bell inequalities (including one that was specifically espoused by Feynman), and
explore the ways in which they demolish the arguments in favor of local hidden-variable theories. We
also examine the roots of Feynman’s attitude toward Bell’s theorem in the context of Feynman’s special
perspective on quantum mechanics.
1. Introduction. Quantum weirdness is rooted in the fact that the states of a quantum system have
probability amplitudes, that these amplitudes are complex numbers, and that the evolution,
superposition, and combination of these complex amplitudes give rise to phenomena that often
seem strange, counterintuitive, and outright paradoxical to the worldview that is firmly rooted in our
understanding of classical physics, where probability amplitudes play no role. Richard Feynman has
consistently and persistently emphasized the importance of probability amplitudes in his teachings
and his descriptions of quantum phenomena.1,2 In fact, his path integral formulation of quantum
mechanics is based on the fundamental idea that one must add up all the probability amplitudes that
contribute to an event along different paths — so long as the paths are physically allowed and are, in
principle, indistinguishable from one another.3 The squared magnitude of the sum total of these
complex amplitudes will then yield the ordinary probability of occurrence of the event.1-3
Given Feynman’s profound understanding of physics, in general, and of quantum mechanics, in
particular, one would be inclined to think that he had reached the point where quantum weirdness
no longer disturbed him. Yet, as late as 1982, he would write:4 “we always have had a great deal of
difficulty in understanding the world view that quantum mechanics represents. At least I do, because I’m an old
enough man that I haven’t got to the point that this stuff is obvious to me. Okay, I still get nervous with it.” In
the same paper,4 Feynman describes an experiment with a pair of polarization entangled photons
which demonstrates the incompatibility of quantum mechanical predictions with the existence of
local hidden variables. While the argument is very much in line with John Bell’s views on the
subject,5-7 Feynman does not credit Bell, and indeed appears to have quietly known and internalized
the implications of such local hidden-variable theories (LHVTs) for quite some time.8,9 Be it as it
may, the goal of the present paper is not to adjudicate the issue for purposes of parceling out
historical credit, but rather to provide an accessible account of Bell’s inequalities that is informed
by Feynman’s special perspective on quantum mechanics — specifically, his belief in the primacy
of probability amplitudes.1-4
The organization of the paper is as follows. The maximally entangled photon pair discussed by
Feynman in the aforementioned paper4 is the subject of Sec.2. Here, we begin by describing the
polarization state of the photon pair, then present the quantum mechanical explanation of
experiments in which each photon passes through a linear polarizer (also known as polarization
analyzer) before being detected. This is followed by a concise argument as to why any LHVT
cannot possibly explain the observed correlations in certain experiments of the sort. In the particular
arrangement of polarizers chosen by Feynman, the probability of agreement between the signals of