The Categories(范畴)

VIP免费
2024-12-26 1 0 137.93KB 38 页 5.9玖币
侵权投诉
The Categories
1
The Categories
By Aristotle
Translated by E. M. Edghill
The Categories
2
Section 1
Part 1
Things are said to be named 'equivocally' when, though they have a
common name, the definition corresponding with the name differs for
each. Thus, a real man and a figure in a picture can both lay claim to the
name 'animal'; yet these are equivocally so named, for, though they have a
common name, the definition corresponding with the name differs for
each. For should any one define in what sense each is an animal, his
definition in the one case will be appropriate to that case only.
On the other hand, things are said to be named 'univocally' which have
both the name and the definition answering to the name in common. A
man and an ox are both 'animal', and these are univocally so named,
inasmuch as not only the name, but also the definition, is the same in both
cases: for if a man should state in what sense each is an animal, the
statement in the one case would be identical with that in the other.
Things are said to be named 'derivatively', which derive their name
from some other name, but differ from it in termination. Thus the
grammarian derives his name from the word 'grammar', and the
courageous man from the word 'courage'.
Part 2
Forms of speech are either simple or composite. Examples of the latter
are such expressions as 'the man runs', 'the man wins'; of the former 'man',
'ox', 'runs', 'wins'.
Of things themselves some are predicable of a subject, and are never
present in a subject. Thus 'man' is predicable of the individual man, and is
never present in a subject.
By being 'present in a subject' I do not mean present as parts are
present in a whole, but being incapable of existence apart from the said
The Categories
3
subject.
Some things, again, are present in a subject, but are never predicable
of a subject. For instance, a certain point of grammatical knowledge is
present in the mind, but is not predicable of any subject; or again, a certain
whiteness may be present in the body (for colour requires a material basis),
yet it is never predicable of anything.
Other things, again, are both predicable of a subject and present in a
subject. Thus while knowledge is present in the human mind, it is
predicable of grammar.
There is, lastly, a class of things which are neither present in a subject
nor predicable of a subject, such as the individual man or the individual
horse. But, to speak more generally, that which is individual and has the
character of a unit is never predicable of a subject. Yet in some cases there
is nothing to prevent such being present in a subject. Thus a certain point
of grammatical knowledge is present in a subject.
Part 3
When one thing is predicated of another, all that which is predicable of
the predicate will be predicable also of the subject. Thus, 'man' is
predicated of the individual man; but 'animal' is predicated of 'man'; it will,
therefore, be predicable of the individual man also: for the individual man
is both 'man' and 'animal'.
If genera are different and co-ordinate, their differentiae are
themselves different in kind. Take as an instance the genus 'animal' and the
genus 'knowledge'. 'With feet', 'two-footed', 'winged', 'aquatic', are
differentiae of 'animal'; the species of knowledge are not distinguished by
the same differentiae. One species of knowledge does not differ from
another in being 'two-footed'.
But where one genus is subordinate to another, there is nothing to
prevent their having the same differentiae: for the greater class is
predicated of the lesser, so that all the differentiae of the predicate will be
differentiae also of the subject.
The Categories
4
Part 4
Expressions which are in no way composite signify substance,
quantity, quality, relation, place, time, position, state, action, or affection.
To sketch my meaning roughly, examples of substance are 'man' or 'the
horse', of quantity, such terms as 'two cubits long' or 'three cubits long', of
quality, such attributes as 'white', 'grammatical'. 'Double', 'half', 'greater',
fall under the category of relation; 'in a the market place', 'in the Lyceum',
under that of place; 'yesterday', 'last year', under that of time. 'Lying',
'sitting', are terms indicating position, 'shod', 'armed', state; 'to lance', 'to
cauterize', action; 'to be lanced', 'to be cauterized', affection.
No one of these terms, in and by itself, involves an affirmation; it is by
the combination of such terms that positive or negative statements arise.
For every assertion must, as is admitted, be either true or false, whereas
expressions which are not in any way composite such as 'man', 'white',
'runs', 'wins', cannot be either true or false.
Part 5
Substance, in the truest and primary and most definite sense of the
word, is that which is neither predicable of a subject nor present in a
subject; for instance, the individual man or horse. But in a secondary sense
those things are called substances within which, as species, the primary
substances are included; also those which, as genera, include the species.
For instance, the individual man is included in the species 'man', and the
genus to which the species belongs is 'animal'; these, therefore-that is to
say, the species 'man' and the genus 'animal,-are termed secondary
substances.
It is plain from what has been said that both the name and the
definition of the predicate must be predicable of the subject. For instance,
'man' is predicted of the individual man. Now in this case the name of the
species man' is applied to the individual, for we use the term 'man' in
describing the individual; and the definition of 'man' will also be
predicated of the individual man, for the individual man is both man and
The Categories
5
animal. Thus, both the name and the definition of the species are
predicable of the individual.
With regard, on the other hand, to those things which are present in a
subject, it is generally the case that neither their name nor their definition
is predicable of that in which they are present. Though, however, the
definition is never predicable, there is nothing in certain cases to prevent
the name being used. For instance, 'white' being present in a body is
predicated of that in which it is present, for a body is called white: the
definition, however, of the colour white' is never predicable of the body.
Everything except primary substances is either predicable of a primary
substance or present in a primary substance. This becomes evident by
reference to particular instances which occur. 'Animal' is predicated of the
species 'man', therefore of the individual man, for if there were no
individual man of whom it could be predicated, it could not be predicated
of the species 'man' at all. Again, colour is present in body, therefore in
individual bodies, for if there were no individual body in which it was
present, it could not be present in body at all. Thus everything except
primary substances is either predicated of primary substances, or is present
in them, and if these last did not exist, it would be impossible for anything
else to exist.
Of secondary substances, the species is more truly substance than the
genus, being more nearly related to primary substance. For if any one
should render an account of what a primary substance is, he would render
a more instructive account, and one more proper to the subject, by stating
the species than by stating the genus. Thus, he would give a more
instructive account of an individual man by stating that he was man than
by stating that he was animal, for the former description is peculiar to the
individual in a greater degree, while the latter is too general. Again, the
man who gives an account of the nature of an individual tree will give a
more instructive account by mentioning the species 'tree' than by
mentioning the genus 'plant'.
Moreover, primary substances are most properly called substances in
virtue of the fact that they are the entities which underlie every. else, and
that everything else is either predicated of them or present in them. Now
The Categories
6
the same relation which subsists between primary substance and
everything else subsists also between the species and the genus: for the
species is to the genus as subject is to predicate, since the genus is
predicated of the species, whereas the species cannot be predicated of the
genus. Thus we have a second ground for asserting that the species is more
truly substance than the genus.
Of species themselves, except in the case of such as are genera, no one
is more truly substance than another. We should not give a more
appropriate account of the individual man by stating the species to which
he belonged, than we should of an individual horse by adopting the same
method of definition. In the same way, of primary substances, no one is
more truly substance than another; an individual man is not more truly
substance than an individual ox.
It is, then, with good reason that of all that remains, when we exclude
primary substances, we concede to species and genera alone the name
'secondary substance', for these alone of all the predicates convey a
knowledge of primary substance. For it is by stating the species or the
genus that we appropriately define any individual man; and we shall make
our definition more exact by stating the former than by stating the latter.
All other things that we state, such as that he is white, that he runs, and so
on, are irrelevant to the definition. Thus it is just that these alone, apart
from primary substances, should be called substances.
Further, primary substances are most properly so called, because they
underlie and are the subjects of everything else. Now the same relation
that subsists between primary substance and everything else subsists also
between the species and the genus to which the primary substance belongs,
on the one hand, and every attribute which is not included within these, on
the other. For these are the subjects of all such. If we call an individual
man 'skilled in grammar', the predicate is applicable also to the species and
to the genus to which he belongs. This law holds good in all cases.
It is a common characteristic of all sub. stance that it is never present
in a subject. For primary substance is neither present in a subject nor
predicated of a subject; while, with regard to secondary substances, it is
clear from the following arguments (apart from others) that they are not
The Categories
7
present in a subject. For 'man' is predicated of the individual man, but is
not present in any subject: for manhood is not present in the individual
man. In the same way, 'animal' is also predicated of the individual man,
but is not present in him. Again, when a thing is present in a subject,
though the name may quite well be applied to that in which it is present,
the definition cannot be applied. Yet of secondary substances, not only the
name, but also the definition, applies to the subject: we should use both
the definition of the species and that of the genus with reference to the
individual man. Thus substance cannot be present in a subject.
Yet this is not peculiar to substance, for it is also the case that
differentiae cannot be present in subjects. The characteristics 'terrestrial'
and 'two-footed' are predicated of the species 'man', but not present in it.
For they are not in man. Moreover, the definition of the differentia may be
predicated of that of which the differentia itself is predicated. For instance,
if the characteristic 'terrestrial' is predicated of the species 'man', the
definition also of that characteristic may be used to form the predicate of
the species 'man': for 'man' is terrestrial.
The fact that the parts of substances appear to be present in the whole,
as in a subject, should not make us apprehensive lest we should have to
admit that such parts are not substances: for in explaining the phrase
'being present in a subject', we stated' that we meant 'otherwise than as
parts in a whole'.
It is the mark of substances and of differentiae that, in all propositions
of which they form the predicate, they are predicated univocally. For all
such propositions have for their subject either the individual or the species.
It is true that, inasmuch as primary substance is not predicable of anything,
it can never form the predicate of any proposition. But of secondary
substances, the species is predicated of the individual, the genus both of
the species and of the individual. Similarly the differentiae are predicated
of the species and of the individuals. Moreover, the definition of the
species and that of the genus are applicable to the primary substance, and
that of the genus to the species. For all that is predicated of the predicate
will be predicated also of the subject. Similarly, the definition of the
differentiae will be applicable to the species and to the individuals. But it
The Categories
8
was stated above that the word 'univocal' was applied to those things
which had both name and definition in common. It is, therefore,
established that in every proposition, of which either substance or a
differentia forms the predicate, these are predicated univocally.
All substance appears to signify that which is individual. In the case of
primary substance this is indisputably true, for the thing is a unit. In the
case of secondary substances, when we speak, for instance, of 'man' or
'animal', our form of speech gives the impression that we are here also
indicating that which is individual, but the impression is not strictly true;
for a secondary substance is not an individual, but a class with a certain
qualification; for it is not one and single as a primary substance is; the
words 'man', 'animal', are predicable of more than one subject.
Yet species and genus do not merely indicate quality, like the term
'white'; 'white' indicates quality and nothing further, but species and genus
determine the quality with reference to a substance: they signify substance
qualitatively differentiated. The determinate qualification covers a larger
field in the case of the genus that in that of the species: he who uses the
word 'animal' is herein using a word of wider extension than he who uses
the word 'man'.
Another mark of substance is that it has no contrary. What could be the
contrary of any primary substance, such as the individual man or animal?
It has none. Nor can the species or the genus have a contrary. Yet this
characteristic is not peculiar to substance, but is true of many other things,
such as quantity. There is nothing that forms the contrary of 'two cubits
long' or of 'three cubits long', or of 'ten', or of any such term. A man may
contend that 'much' is the contrary of 'little', or 'great' of 'small', but of
definite quantitative terms no contrary exists.
Substance, again, does not appear to admit of variation of degree. I do
not mean by this that one substance cannot be more or less truly substance
than another, for it has already been stated' that this is the case; but that no
single substance admits of varying degrees within itself. For instance, one
particular substance, 'man', cannot be more or less man either than himself
at some other time or than some other man. One man cannot be more man
than another, as that which is white may be more or less white than some
摘要:

TheCategories1TheCategoriesByAristotleTranslatedbyE.M.EdghillTheCategories2Section1Part1Thingsaresaidtobenamed'equivocally'when,thoughtheyhaveacommonname,thedefinitioncorrespondingwiththenamediffersforeach.Thus,arealmanandafigureinapicturecanbothlayclaimtothename'animal';yettheseareequivocallysoname...

展开>> 收起<<
The Categories(范畴).pdf

共38页,预览8页

还剩页未读, 继续阅读

声明:本站为文档C2C交易模式,即用户上传的文档直接被用户下载,本站只是中间服务平台,本站所有文档下载所得的收益归上传人(含作者)所有。玖贝云文库仅提供信息存储空间,仅对用户上传内容的表现方式做保护处理,对上载内容本身不做任何修改或编辑。若文档所含内容侵犯了您的版权或隐私,请立即通知玖贝云文库,我们立即给予删除!
分类:外语学习 价格:5.9玖币 属性:38 页 大小:137.93KB 格式:PDF 时间:2024-12-26

开通VIP享超值会员特权

  • 多端同步记录
  • 高速下载文档
  • 免费文档工具
  • 分享文档赚钱
  • 每日登录抽奖
  • 优质衍生服务
/ 38
客服
关注